2025婵犵數濮烽弫鍛婃叏閻戣棄鏋侀柛娑橈攻閸欏繘鏌i幋锝嗩棄闁哄绶氶弻娑樷槈濮楀牊鏁鹃梺鍛婄懃缁绘﹢寮婚悢铏圭<闁靛繒濮甸悘宥夋⒑缁嬪潡顎楁い锔诲灦閳ワ箓宕稿Δ浣告疂闂傚倸鐗婄粙鎴︼綖瀹€鈧槐鎾存媴閸濆嫮褰欓梺鎼炲劀閸滀礁鏅i梻浣筋嚙鐎涒晝绮欓幒鏇熸噷闂佽绻愬ù姘跺储婵傚憡绠掓繝鐢靛Т閿曘倝骞婃惔銏㈩洸闁诡垼鐏旀惔銊ョ倞鐟滄繈鐓鈧埞鎴﹀灳瀹曞洤鐓熼悗瑙勬礈閸犳牠銆佸鈧幃娆忣啅椤旈敮鍋撻幘顔解拻闁稿本鐟чˇ锕傛煙鐠囇呯瘈闁诡喚鍏樻俊鐤槼鐎规洖寮堕幈銊ヮ渻鐠囪弓澹曢柣搴㈩問閸犳牠鈥﹂悜钘夋瀬闁归偊鍘肩欢鐐测攽閻樻彃顏撮柛姘嚇濮婄粯鎷呴悷閭﹀殝缂備浇顕ч崐姝岀亱濡炪倖鎸鹃崐锝呪槈閵忕姷顦板銈嗘尵婵兘鏁嶅⿰鍫熲拺缂備焦锚婵箓鏌涢幘瀵告噰鐎规洘绻堟俊鍫曞幢濞嗘埈鍟庣紓浣鸿檸閸欏啴藟閹捐泛濮柍褜鍓熼幃妤€鈻撻崹顔界亪濡炪値鍘鹃崗姗€鐛崘顔碱潊闁靛牆鎳庣粣娑欑節閻㈤潧孝閻庢凹鍠涢崐鎾⒒閸屾艾鈧绮堟笟鈧獮澶愭晸閻樿尙顔囬梺绯曞墲缁嬫垵顔忓┑鍥ヤ簻闁哄啫鍊婚幗鍌炴煕閻旈攱鍣界紒杈ㄦ崌瀹曟帒顫濋钘変壕闁归棿绀佺壕褰掓煟閹达絽袚闁搞倕瀚伴弻銈夊箹娴h閿梺鎼炲妽濮婂綊濡甸崟顖氱闁告鍋熸禒濂告⒑閹肩偛濡奸柛濠傛健瀵鈽夐姀鈺傛櫇闂佹寧绻傚Λ娑⑺囬妷鈺傗拺闁芥ê顦弳鐔兼煕閻樺磭澧电€殿喖顭峰鎾偄閾忚鍟庨梻浣虹帛閸旓箓宕滃鑸靛仧闁哄洢鍨洪埛鎴犵磼鐎n偒鍎ラ柛搴$箲娣囧﹪顢曢敐鍥╃杽閻庢鍠涢褔鍩ユ径濠庢僵妞ゆ劧绲芥刊浼存⒒娴e憡鍟為柟绋挎閸┾偓妞ゆ巻鍋撻崡閬嶆煕椤愶絿绠ユ繛鎾愁煼閺屾洟宕煎┑鍥ф畻闂佺粯绋掔划鎾诲蓟閻旂厧绀勯柕鍫濇椤忥拷4闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁诡垎鍐f寖闂佺娅曢幑鍥灳閺冨牆绀冩い蹇庣娴滈箖鏌ㄥ┑鍡欏嚬缂併劌銈搁弻鐔兼儌閸濄儳袦闂佸搫鐭夌紞渚€銆佸鈧幃娆撳箹椤撶噥妫ч梻鍌欑窔濞佳兾涘▎鎴炴殰闁圭儤顨愮紞鏍ㄧ節闂堟侗鍎愰柡鍛叀閺屾稑鈽夐崡鐐差潻濡炪們鍎查懝楣冨煘閹寸偛绠犻梺绋匡攻椤ㄥ棝骞堥妸鈺傚€婚柦妯侯槺閿涙盯姊虹紒妯哄闁稿簺鍊濆畷鎴犫偓锝庡枟閻撶喐淇婇婵嗗惞婵犫偓娴犲鐓冪憸婊堝礂濞戞碍顐芥慨姗嗗墻閸ゆ洟鏌熺紒銏犳灈妞ゎ偄鎳橀弻宥夊煛娴e憡娈查梺缁樼箖濞茬喎顫忕紒妯诲闁芥ê锛嶉幘缁樼叆婵﹩鍘规禍婊堟煥閺冨浂鍤欓柡瀣ㄥ€楃槐鎺撴綇閵婏富妫冮悗娈垮枟閹歌櫕鎱ㄩ埀顒勬煃闁款垰浜鹃梺褰掝棑缁垳鎹㈠☉娆愮秶闁告挆鍛呮艾鈹戦悙鍙夊珔缂佹彃娼″顐︻敊鐏忔牗顫嶉梺闈涢獜缁辨洟宕㈤柆宥嗏拺闁告繂瀚弳濠囨煕鐎n偅灏扮紒缁樼洴閹崇娀顢楅埀顒勫几濞戙垺鐓熸繛鎴濆船濞呭秶鈧鍠曠划娆撱€佸Ο娆炬Ъ闂佸搫鎳忕换鍫濐潖濞差亝顥堟繛鎴炶壘椤e搫鈹戦悙棰濆殝缂佽尪娉曢崚鎺楊敇閻旈绐炴繝鐢靛Т鐎涒晝鈧潧鐭傚娲濞戞艾顣哄┑鈽嗗亝缁嬫帡寮查崼鏇熺劶鐎广儱妫涢崢閬嶆煟鎼搭垳绉甸柛鎾寸懄缁傛帡鏌嗗鍡欏幍濡炪倖娲栧Λ娑氬姬閳ь剚绻濈喊澶岀?闁稿繑锕㈠畷娲晸閻樿尙锛滃┑鐘诧工閸燁偆绮诲ú顏呪拻闁稿本鐟чˇ锕傛煙绾板崬浜滈悡銈夋煏婵炵偓娅呯痪鍓х帛缁绘盯骞嬪▎蹇曚患闂佺粯甯掗悘姘跺Φ閸曨垰绠抽柛鈩冦仦婢规洘绻濋悽闈浶涢柛瀣崌濮婃椽顢楅埀顒傜矓閹绢喗鍊块柛顭戝亖娴滄粓鏌熼崫鍕ラ柛蹇撶焸閺屾盯鎮㈤崫銉ュ绩闂佸搫鐬奸崰鏍х暦濞嗘挸围闁糕剝顨忔导锟�8闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁诡垎鍐f寖闂佺娅曢幑鍥灳閺冨牆绀冩い蹇庣娴滈箖鏌ㄥ┑鍡欏嚬缂併劌銈搁弻鐔兼儌閸濄儳袦闂佸搫鐭夌紞渚€銆佸鈧幃娆撳箹椤撶噥妫ч梻鍌欑窔濞佳兾涘▎鎴炴殰闁圭儤顨愮紞鏍ㄧ節闂堟侗鍎愰柡鍛叀閺屾稑鈽夐崡鐐差潻濡炪們鍎查懝楣冨煘閹寸偛绠犻梺绋匡攻椤ㄥ棝骞堥妸鈺傚€婚柦妯侯槺閿涙盯姊虹紒妯哄闁稿簺鍊濆畷鎴犫偓锝庡枟閻撶喐淇婇婵嗗惞婵犫偓娴犲鐓冪憸婊堝礂濞戞碍顐芥慨姗嗗墻閸ゆ洟鏌熺紒銏犳灈妞ゎ偄鎳橀弻宥夊煛娴e憡娈查梺缁樼箖閻楃姴顫忕紒妯肩懝闁逞屽墴閸┾偓妞ゆ帒鍊告禒婊堟煠濞茶鐏¢柡鍛埣楠炲秹顢欓崜褝绱叉俊鐐€栧ú鏍涘☉銏犵濞寸厧鐡ㄩ幊姘舵煛瀹ュ海浜圭憸鐗堝笚閺呮煡鏌涢銈呮珡濞寸姭鏅涢—鍐Χ閸℃ǚ鎷瑰┑鐐跺皺閸犲酣锝炶箛鎾佹椽顢旈崨顓濈敾闂備浇顫夐鏍窗濡ゅ懎绠熷┑鍌氭啞閳锋垿鏌ゆ慨鎰偓鏇㈠几閸岀偞鐓曢幖杈剧稻閺嗩剚顨ラ悙鎻掓殭妞ゎ偅绮撻崺鈧い鎺戝閺勩儵鏌ㄩ悢鍝勑㈢紒鈧崘鈹夸簻闊洦鎸婚敍鏃傜磼鏉堛劎鍙€婵﹦绮幏鍛存惞閻熸壆顐奸梻浣藉吹閸犲棝宕归挊澶屾殾闁硅揪绠戠粻鑽ょ磽娴h疮缂氶柛姗€浜跺娲濞淬劌缍婂畷鏇㈠箮閽樺妲梺鎸庣箓濞茬娀宕戦幘鏂ユ灁闁割煈鍠楅悘鍫濐渻閵堝骸寮柡鈧潏銊р攳濠电姴娲ょ粻鐟懊归敐鍛喐闁告ɑ鎮傚铏圭矙閹稿孩鎷遍梺娲诲弾閸犳岸鎳炴潏銊ь浄閻庯綆鍋€閹风粯绻涙潏鍓у埌闁硅櫕鐟ㄩ妵鎰板箳閹存繄褰夋俊鐐€栫敮鎺楀磹婵犳碍鍎楁繛鍡樻尰閻撴瑩寮堕崼鐔峰姢闁伙附绮撻弻鈩冩媴缁嬪簱鍋撻崸妤€钃熼柕濞炬櫆閸嬪棝鏌涚仦鍓р槈妞ゅ骏鎷� 闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁诡垎鍐f寖闂佺娅曢幑鍥灳閺冨牆绀冩い蹇庣娴滈箖鏌ㄥ┑鍡欏嚬缂併劌銈搁弻鐔兼儌閸濄儳袦闂佸搫鐭夌紞渚€銆佸鈧幃娆撳箹椤撶噥妫ч梻鍌欑窔濞佳兾涘▎鎴炴殰闁圭儤顨愮紞鏍ㄧ節闂堟侗鍎愰柡鍛叀閺屾稑鈽夐崡鐐差潻濡炪們鍎查懝楣冨煘閹寸偛绠犻梺绋匡攻椤ㄥ棝骞堥妸鈺傚€婚柦妯侯槺閿涙盯姊虹紒妯哄闁稿簺鍊濆畷鎴犫偓锝庡枟閻撶喐淇婇婵嗗惞婵犫偓娴犲鐓冪憸婊堝礂濞戞碍顐芥慨姗嗗墻閸ゆ洟鏌熺紒銏犳灈妞ゎ偄鎳橀弻锝呂熼懡銈呯仼闂佹悶鍎崝搴ㄥ储闁秵鐓熼煫鍥ㄦ礀娴犳粌顭胯缁瑩骞冮敓鐙€鏁嶆慨妯垮亹閸炵敻鏌i悢鍝ユ噧閻庢凹鍘剧划鍫ュ焵椤掑嫭鈷戦悗鍦濞兼劙鏌涢妸銉﹀仴闁靛棔绀侀埢搴ㄥ箣閻樼绱查梻浣筋潐閸庤櫕鏅舵惔锝囩幓婵°倕鎳忛埛鎺懨归敐鍛暈闁哥喓鍋為妵鍕敇閻愭惌妫﹂悗瑙勬礃閿曘垽寮幇鏉垮耿婵炲棗鑻禍鐐箾瀹割喕绨奸柛濠傜仛椤ㄣ儵鎮欓懠顑胯檸闂佸憡姊圭喊宥囨崲濞戙垺鍤戞い鎺嗗亾闁宠鐗忛埀顒冾潐濞叉﹢宕归崸妤冨祦婵せ鍋撻柟铏矒濡啫鈽夊▎鎴斿亾椤撱垺鈷掑ù锝呮啞閸熺偞绻涚拠褏鐣电€规洘绮岄埥澶愬閳╁啯鐝繝鐢靛仦閸垶宕瑰ú顏勭厱闁硅揪闄勯悡鏇熺箾閹寸們姘舵儑鐎n偆绠鹃柛顐ゅ枑缁€鈧梺瀹狀潐閸ㄥ潡骞冨▎鎴炲珰鐟滄垿宕ラ锔解拺閻犲洠鈧櫕鐏嗛梺鍛婎殕婵炲﹪濡存担鍓叉僵閻犻缚娅i崝锕€顪冮妶鍡楀潑闁稿鎹囬弻锝夋晲閸パ冨箣閻庤娲栭妶绋款嚕閹绢喖惟闁挎棁濮ら悵婊勭節閻㈤潧袨闁搞劎鍘ч埢鏂库槈閵忊晜鏅為梺绯曞墲閵囨盯寮稿澶嬪€堕柣鎰礋閹烘缁╁ù鐘差儐閻撶喐淇婇婵囶仩濞寸姵鐩弻锟犲幢韫囨梹鐝旈梺瀹狀潐閸ㄥ潡銆佸▎鎾村殟闁靛鍎遍弨顓熶繆閵堝洤啸闁稿鐩弫鍐Ψ閵夘喖娈梺鍛婃处閸ㄦ壆绮诲☉娆嶄簻闁圭儤鍨垫禍鎵磼闁秳鎲炬慨濠勭帛閹峰懐绮电€n偆绉烽柣搴ゎ潐濞叉﹢鏁冮姀銈冣偓浣割潩閹颁焦鈻岄梻浣告惈鐞氼偊宕濋幋鐐扮箚闁割偅娲栭獮銏ゆ煛閸モ晛啸闁伙綁绠栧缁樼瑹閳ь剙岣胯閹囧幢濞嗗苯浜炬慨妯煎帶閻忥妇鈧娲橀〃鍛存偩濠靛绀嬫い鎺戝€搁獮鍫熺節绾版ɑ顫婇柛銊ョ-閸掓帡顢涘杈ㄦ闁诲繒鍋熼崑鎾诲矗韫囨挴鏀介柣妯哄级閸g儤銇勮箛鏇炩枅闁哄苯绉烽¨渚€鏌涢幘瀵告噧闁挎洏鍨哄ḿ蹇涘Ω閿曗偓瀵潡姊哄Ч鍥х伄閺嬵亝娼诲┑瀣拺闁告稑锕ゆ慨锕€霉濠婂懎浠у瑙勬礃缁轰粙宕ㄦ繝鍕笚闁荤喐绮嶇划鎾崇暦濠婂喚娼╅弶鍫氭櫇閻e爼姊虹紒妯烩拻闁告鍥ㄥ€块柛顭戝亖娴滄粓鏌熼崫鍕棞濞存粍鍎抽—鍐Χ閸℃ḿ鈹涚紓鍌氱С缁舵岸鎮伴鑺ュ劅闁靛⿵绠戝▓鐔兼⒑闂堟侗妲堕柛搴㈠閼鸿鲸绻濆顓涙嫽婵炶揪绲肩拃锕傚绩娴煎瓨鐓曢悗锝庡亜婵秶鈧娲橀崹浣冪亽闂佽壈顫夊妯虹毈婵犵數濮烽弫鍛婃叏閻㈤潧鏋堢€广儱顦悡鏇㈡煙鏉堥箖妾柣鎾存礋閺岀喖鏌囬敃鈧晶顔剧磼閻欐瑥娲﹂悡娆愩亜閺嶃劍鐨戝褝绠撻弻锛勪沪閸撗€濮囩紓浣虹帛缁诲牆鐣烽幒妤€围闁搞儜鍕偓顖炴⒑鐠囧弶鍞夋い顐㈩槸鐓ら柍鍝勫暟缁€濠傘€掑锝呬壕閻庤娲樺浠嬪春閳ь剚銇勯幒宥夋濞存粍绮撻弻鐔兼倻濡櫣浠村銈呮禋娴滎亪寮诲澶嬬叆閻庯綆浜炴导宀勬⒑閸濆嫭婀扮紒瀣灴閸╃偤骞嬮敃鈧獮銏′繆閵堝拑姊楃紒杈ㄦ尰娣囧﹪鎮欓鍕ㄥ亾閵堝纾婚柟鎯у娑撳秹鏌熼幑鎰靛殭闁藉啰鍠愮换娑㈠箣濞嗗繒浠肩紓渚囧亜缁夊綊寮诲鍫闂佸憡鎸鹃崰搴ㄦ偩閻ゎ垬浜归柟鐑樺灴閺佹粌鈹戞幊閸婃洟宕銈囩焾闁挎洖鍊归埛鎴︽煕濞戞﹫宸ュ┑顕嗙畵閺屾盯鎮╁畷鍥р吂濠电偞褰冮悘婵嬪煘閹达附鍋愭い鏃囧亹娴煎洤鈹戦悙宸Ч闁烩晩鍨跺顐﹀礃椤旇姤娅囬梺绋挎湰缁嬫帒鈻嶉弽褉鏀介柣妯款嚋瀹搞儵鏌涢悢鍝勨枅鐎殿喓鍔嶇粋鎺斺偓锝庡亞閸樹粙姊鸿ぐ鎺戜喊闁告ḿ鏅槐鐐哄箣閿旂晫鍘介棅顐㈡储閸庢娊鎮鹃悽鍛婄厸閻忕偠顕ф慨鍌溾偓娈垮枟濞兼瑨鐏冩繛杈剧到濠€杈亹閸℃稒鈷戦悹鍥ㄧ叀閸欏嫭绻涙担鍐叉搐鍥撮梺褰掓?缁€渚€寮告笟鈧弻鐔煎礈瑜忕敮娑㈡煛閸涱喗鍊愰柡灞诲姂閹倝宕掑☉姗嗕紦闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁诡垎鍐f寖闂佺娅曢幑鍥灳閺冨牆绀冩い蹇庣娴滈箖鏌ㄥ┑鍡欏嚬缂併劎绮妵鍕箳鐎n亞浠鹃梺闈涙搐鐎氫即鐛崶顒夋晬婵絾瀵ч幑鍥蓟閻斿摜鐟归柛顭戝枛椤牆顪冮妶搴′簼缂侇喗鎸搁悾鐑藉础閻愬秵妫冮崺鈧い鎺戝瀹撲礁鈹戦悩鎻掝伀缁惧彞绮欓弻娑氫沪閹规劕顥濋梺閫炲苯澧伴柟铏崌閿濈偛鈹戠€n€晠鏌嶆潪鎷屽厡闁汇倕鎳愮槐鎾存媴閸撴彃鍓卞銈嗗灦閻熲晛鐣烽妷褉鍋撻敐搴℃灍闁绘挻娲橀妵鍕箛闂堟稐绨肩紓浣藉煐濮樸劎妲愰幘璇茬闁冲搫鍊婚ˇ鏉库攽椤旂》榫氭繛鍜冪秮楠炲繘鎮╃拠鑼舵憰闂侀潧顦介崰鎺楀磻閹炬緞鏃堝川椤旀儳骞堟繝纰樻閸ㄩ潧鐣烽悽鍛婂剹闁圭儤鏌¢崑鎾舵喆閸曨剛顦ㄩ梺鎼炲妼濞硷繝鎮伴鍢夌喖鎳栭埡鍐跨床婵犵妲呴崹鎶藉储瑜旈悰顕€宕奸妷锔规嫽婵炶揪绲介幉锟犲箚閸喓绠鹃悘鐐插€搁悘鑼偓瑙勬礃缁诲嫭绂掗敃鍌氱鐟滄粌煤閹间焦鈷戠紓浣姑慨澶愭煕鎼存稑鈧繈骞冮敓鐘参ㄩ柨鏂垮⒔椤旀洟姊洪悷閭﹀殶闁稿鍠栭獮濠囧川椤斿墽顔曢梺鍦帛鐢偤骞楅悩缁樼厵濞撴艾鐏濇俊鐣岀磼缂佹ḿ绠炵€规洘锕㈤崺鐐村緞濮濆本顎楅梻鍌氬€峰ù鍥敋閺嶎厼绐楁慨妯挎硾缁€鍌涗繆椤栨瑨顒熼柛銈嗘礋閺屻倗绮欑捄銊ょ驳闂佺ǹ娴烽崰鏍蓟閻斿吋鍊锋い鎺嶈兌缁嬪洭姊烘导娆戠暢濞存粠鍓涘Σ鎰板箻鐠囪尙锛滃┑顔斤供閸忔﹢宕戦幘鎼Ч閹兼番鍩勯崑銊╂⒑鐠恒劌鏋斿┑顔芥尦濮婂顢涘☉鏍︾盎闂佸搫娲﹂〃鍛妤e啯鍊甸悷娆忓缁€鈧紓鍌氱Т閿曘倝鎮鹃柨瀣檮缂佸鐏濆畵鍡涙⒑缂佹ê濮夐柡浣规倐瀵娊顢曢敂瑙f嫽婵炶揪缍€婵倗娑甸崼鏇熺厱闁绘ǹ娅曠亸浼存煙娓氬灝濮傛鐐达耿椤㈡瑩鎳栭埡濠冩暏闂傚倷娴囬~澶愬磿閸忓吋鍙忛柕鍫濐槹閸嬪倿鐓崶銊с€掗柛娆愭崌閺屾盯濡烽敐鍛闂佸憡鏌i崐妤呮儉椤忓牆绠氱憸搴ㄥ磻閵夆晜鐓涢悘鐐插⒔閳藉鎽堕敐澶嬬厱闊洦鎸搁幃鎴炴叏閿濆懐澧曢柍瑙勫灴椤㈡瑧娑靛畡鏉款潬缂傚倷绶¢崳顕€宕瑰畷鍥у灊妞ゆ挶鍨洪崑鍕煟閹捐櫕鎹i柛濠勫仱閹嘲饪伴崘顎綁鎮楅棃娑樻倯闁诡垱妫冮弫鎰板炊閳哄闂繝鐢靛仩閹活亞寰婃禒瀣妞ゆ劧绲挎晶锟犳⒒閸屾瑧鍔嶉柟顔肩埣瀹曟繄浠︾紒鎾剁窗闂佽法鍠撴慨瀵哥不閺嶎灐褰掑礂閸忕厧鍓归梺杞扮閿曪箓鎯€椤忓牆绠€光偓閸曨偅鎳欓柣搴e仯閸婃牕顪冮挊澶樻綎婵炲樊浜濋悞濠氭煟閹邦垰钄奸悗姘緲椤儻顦叉い鏇ㄥ弮閸┾偓妞ゆ帊绶¢崯蹇涙煕閻樺磭澧甸柍銉畵閹粓鎸婃径瀣偓顒勬⒑瑜版帒浜伴柛妯垮亹濞嗐垽鎮欑紙鐘电畾濡炪倖鐗楃划搴f暜濞戞瑧绠鹃柛娑卞幘鏁堝┑顔硷功缁垶骞忛崨瀛樻優闁荤喐澹嗛濂告⒒娴h鍋犻柛鏃€鍨靛玻鑳槾闁告瑥鎳樺娲濞戞艾顣哄┑鈽嗗亝閻熲晛鐣烽敐鍫㈢杸闁哄啫鍊婚鏇㈡⒑閻熸壆鎽犻柣鐔村劦閹﹢顢旈崼鐔哄帗闂備礁鐏濋鍛存倶鐎涙ɑ鍙忓┑鐘插暞閵囨繃銇勯姀鈩冪濠碘€崇埣瀹曘劑顢楅崒娑樼闂傚倸鍊风粈渚€宕ョ€n亶娓婚柛褎顨呴崹鍌炴⒑椤掆偓缁夋挳鎮挎ィ鍐╃厱妞ゆ劧绲炬径鍕煛娴i潻韬柡灞剧洴楠炴ê螖閳ь剟骞忛幋鐘愁潟闁规儼濮ら悡鐔煎箹鏉堝墽纾块柣锝庡弮閺屾稒鎯旈妸銈嗗枤濡ょ姷鍋涚换姗€鐛€n亖鏀介柟閭﹀墯濞呭﹪姊绘笟鈧ḿ褔藝椤撱垹纾块柟鎯版濮规煡鏌涢埄鍐姇闁绘挶鍎茬换婵嬫濞戞瑯妫″銈冨劜缁秹濡甸崟顖氬嵆闁绘棁娅i悡鍌滅磽娴d粙鍝洪悽顖滃仧濡叉劙骞掗幊宕囧枛閹虫牠鍩¢崘鈺傤啌婵犵绱曢崑鎴﹀磹閵堝纾婚柛娑卞灡瀹曟煡鏌涢鐘插姌闁逞屽厸缁€浣界亙闂佸憡渚楅崢楣冩晬濠婂牊鈷戦梻鍫熺〒婢ф洟鏌熼崘鑼鐎殿喗濞婇崺锟犲川椤旇瀚介梻浣呵归張顒勬嚌妤e啫鐒垫い鎺嗗亾闁搞垺鐓″﹢渚€姊洪幖鐐插妧闁逞屽墴瀵悂寮介鐔哄幐闂佹悶鍎崕閬嶆倶閳哄懏鈷掗柛灞诲€曢悘锕傛煛鐏炶濮傜€殿喗鎸抽幃娆徝圭€n亙澹曢梺鍛婄缚閸庤櫕绋夊鍡愪簻闁哄稁鍋勬禒锕傛煟閹惧崬鍔﹂柡宀嬬秮瀵挳鎮欏ù瀣壕闁革富鍘搁崑鎾愁潩閻愵剙顏�3闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁诡垎鍐f寖闂佺娅曢幑鍥灳閺冨牆绀冩い蹇庣娴滈箖鏌ㄥ┑鍡欏嚬缂併劌銈搁弻鐔兼儌閸濄儳袦闂佸搫鐭夌紞渚€銆佸鈧幃娆撳箹椤撶噥妫ч梻鍌欑窔濞佳兾涘▎鎴炴殰闁圭儤顨愮紞鏍ㄧ節闂堟侗鍎愰柡鍛叀閺屾稑鈽夐崡鐐差潻濡炪們鍎查懝楣冨煘閹寸偛绠犻梺绋匡攻椤ㄥ棝骞堥妸鈺傚€婚柦妯侯槺閿涙盯姊虹紒妯哄闁稿簺鍊濆畷鎴犫偓锝庡枟閻撶喐淇婇婵嗗惞婵犫偓娴犲鐓冪憸婊堝礂濞戞碍顐芥慨姗嗗墻閸ゆ洟鏌熺紒銏犳灈妞ゎ偄鎳橀弻宥夊煛娴e憡娈查梺缁樼箖濞茬喎顫忕紒妯诲闁芥ê锛嶉幘缁樼叆婵﹩鍘规禍婊堟煥閺冨浂鍤欓柡瀣ㄥ€楃槐鎺撴綇閵婏富妫冮悗娈垮枟閹歌櫕鎱ㄩ埀顒勬煃闁款垰浜鹃梺褰掝棑缁垳鎹㈠☉娆愮秶闁告挆鍛呮艾鈹戦悙鍙夊珔缂佹彃娼″顐︻敊鐏忔牗顫嶉梺闈涢獜缁辨洟宕㈤柆宥嗏拺闁告繂瀚弳濠囨煕鐎n偅灏扮紒缁樼洴閹崇娀顢楅埀顒勫几濞戙垺鐓熸繛鎴濆船濞呭秶鈧鍠曠划娆撱€佸Ο娆炬Ъ闂佸搫鎳忕换鍫濐潖濞差亝顥堟繛鎴炶壘椤e搫鈹戦悙棰濆殝缂佽尪娉曢崚鎺楊敇閻旈绐炴繝鐢靛Т鐎涒晝鈧潧鐭傚娲濞戞艾顣哄┑鈽嗗亝缁嬫帡寮查崼鏇熺劶鐎广儱妫涢崢閬嶆煟鎼搭垳绉甸柛鎾寸懄缁傛帡鏌嗗鍡欏幍濡炪倖娲栧Λ娑氬姬閳ь剚绻濈喊澶岀?闁稿繑锕㈠畷娲晸閻樿尙锛滃┑鐘诧工閸燁偆绮诲ú顏呪拻闁稿本鐟чˇ锕傛煙绾板崬浜滈悡銈夋煏婵炵偓娅呯痪鍓х帛缁绘盯骞嬪▎蹇曚患闂佺粯甯掗悘姘跺Φ閸曨垰绠抽柛鈩冦仦婢规洘绻濋悽闈浶涢柛瀣崌濮婃椽顢楅埀顒傜矓閹绢喗鍊块柛顭戝亖娴滄粓鏌熼崫鍕ラ柛蹇撶焸閺屾盯鎮㈤崫銉ュ绩闂佸搫鐬奸崰鏍х暦濞嗘挸围闁糕剝顨忔导锟�11闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁诡垎鍐f寖闂佺娅曢幑鍥灳閺冨牆绀冩い蹇庣娴滈箖鏌ㄥ┑鍡欏嚬缂併劌銈搁弻鐔兼儌閸濄儳袦闂佸搫鐭夌紞渚€銆佸鈧幃娆撳箹椤撶噥妫ч梻鍌欑窔濞佳兾涘▎鎴炴殰闁圭儤顨愮紞鏍ㄧ節闂堟侗鍎愰柡鍛叀閺屾稑鈽夐崡鐐差潻濡炪們鍎查懝楣冨煘閹寸偛绠犻梺绋匡攻椤ㄥ棝骞堥妸鈺傚€婚柦妯侯槺閿涙盯姊虹紒妯哄闁稿簺鍊濆畷鎴犫偓锝庡枟閻撶喐淇婇婵嗗惞婵犫偓娴犲鐓冪憸婊堝礂濞戞碍顐芥慨姗嗗墻閸ゆ洟鏌熺紒銏犳灈妞ゎ偄鎳橀弻宥夊煛娴e憡娈查梺缁樼箖閻楃姴顫忕紒妯肩懝闁逞屽墴閸┾偓妞ゆ帒鍊告禒婊堟煠濞茶鐏¢柡鍛埣楠炲秹顢欓崜褝绱叉俊鐐€栧ú鏍涘☉銏犵濞寸厧鐡ㄩ幊姘舵煛瀹ュ海浜圭憸鐗堝笚閺呮煡鏌涢銈呮珡濞寸姭鏅涢—鍐Χ閸℃ǚ鎷瑰┑鐐跺皺閸犲酣锝炶箛鎾佹椽顢旈崨顓濈敾闂備浇顫夐鏍窗濡ゅ懎绠熷┑鍌氭啞閳锋垿鏌ゆ慨鎰偓鏇㈠几閸岀偞鐓曢幖杈剧稻閺嗩剚顨ラ悙鎻掓殭妞ゎ偅绮撻崺鈧い鎺戝閺勩儵鏌ㄩ悢鍝勑㈢紒鈧崘鈹夸簻闊洦鎸婚敍鏃傜磼鏉堛劎鍙€婵﹦绮幏鍛存惞閻熸壆顐奸梻浣藉吹閸犲棝宕归挊澶屾殾闁硅揪绠戠粻鑽ょ磽娴h疮缂氶柛姗€浜跺娲濞淬劌缍婂畷鏇㈠箮閽樺妲梺鎸庣箓濞茬娀宕戦幘鏂ユ灁闁割煈鍠楅悘鍫濐渻閵堝骸寮柡鈧潏銊р攳濠电姴娲ょ粻鐟懊归敐鍛喐闁告ɑ鎮傚铏圭矙閹稿孩鎷遍梺娲诲弾閸犳岸鎳炴潏銊ь浄閻庯綆鍋€閹风粯绻涙潏鍓у埌闁硅櫕鐟ㄩ妵鎰板箳閹存繄褰夋俊鐐€栫敮鎺楀磹婵犳碍鍎楁繛鍡樻尰閻撴瑩寮堕崼鐔峰姢闁伙附绮撻弻鈩冩媴缁嬪簱鍋撻崸妤€钃熼柕濞炬櫆閸嬪棝鏌涚仦鍓р槈妞ゅ骏鎷�
您现在的位置:佛教导航>> 五明研究>> 英文佛教>>正文内容

Causality: Eternal or Momentary?

       

发布时间:2009年04月18日
来源:不详   作者:Winston L. King
人关注  打印  转发  投稿

·期刊原文


Causality: Eternal or Momentary?

By Winston L. King

Philosophy East & West

V. 13 No. 2 (1963) pp. 117-135

Copyright 1963 by University of Hawaii Press

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------


p.117

THIS PAPER Will concern itself with two variant types of causal theory found in Indian philosophy in the eighth and ninth centuries. One of these is Hindu, that of `Sa^mkara, the great commentator of Vedaanta. The other is that of two Buddhist dialectical logicians, `Saantarak.sita and his disciple-commentator Kamala`siila, who in their general position are somewhere in the "idealist" Yogaacaara and "nihilist" Maadhyamika vicinity.

One of the interesting features of the two positions is their sharp difference on some points and yet a curious likeness in others. No doubt their common-though-differently-interpreted heritage from Indian philosophical-religious thought--for Buddhism is a Hindu heresy--accounts for this in general. In particular, it is sometimes suggested[1] that `Saantarak.sita-Kamala`siila may well have influenced the method of `Sa^mkara's exposition and perhaps his thought. At any rate, he was accused of being a crypto-Buddhist despite his attempts to confute the Buddhist position.[2]

D. H. H. Ingalls[3] has construed this confusing likeness-and-difference relation in the following way: `Sa^mkara's version of the Vedaanta proceeds from his basic conviction of the sole reality of the Cosmic Self (Brahman) toward the unreality of the phenomenal world. The Buddhists, on the other hand, begin with their characteristic emphasis upon the evanescence of the phenomenal world and move on from there toward a denial of all substantiality, both in the phenomenal order and in selfhood. Thus, when `Sa^mkara "arrives" at his emphasis on the unreality of the phenomenal world, he speaks much as a Buddhist. But obviously the two denials of phenomenal reality are from opposed viewpoints.

The point of the encounter to be taken up here, as noted above, is in respect to causal theory. This is a crucial point, since, so far as the Vedaanta

p.118

and Buddhism are concerned, it bears on the basic nature of the world order in which we find ourselves; and, more importantly for both, has to do directly and specifically with the human prospects for salvation, i.e., how one reaches his liberating Absolute, "substantial" Brahman, and qualitative, experiential Nirvaa.na, respectively. For, in the causal process, particularly for the Buddhist, is found the key to liberation.

Roughly and generally, the two positions may be set forth thus. `Sa^mkara's fundamental operational base for all his thought is his conviction that Brahman, the Cosmic Self or Supreme Consciousness, is the only true reality. Even the evanescent phenomenal world must be somehow related to Brahman, therefore, for only as Brahman is somehow "in" it can there be a world, however illusory. Hence his preoccupation with the "non-difference" of cause and effect, with its implications of an unchanging basal "substance." The Buddhist position is one of emphasis upon the radical discontinuity of phenomena, the insistence upon the non-identity of cause and effect, and is an unremitting war against all substance theory or implication. But in the end there is a curious static quality about both systems. So far as religious implications are concerned, the Vedaantist finds Buddhist discontinuity a chaos allowing of no definite salvational topography or dependable lines of cause and effect; while the Buddhist is perturbed by the block-universe fixity of Vedaantist substances, including selves, which allows for no saving self-reconstruction. Yet their ultimate liberating Absolutes (Brahman and Nirvaa.na) ate in most ways indistinguishable from each other.

The writings used as a basis for this study are as follows: `Sa^mkara's commentaries on the Brahma Suutra[4] and the B.rhadaara.nyaka Upani.sad:[5] and the Tattvasa^ngraha of `Saantarak.sita, combined with Kamala`siila's commentary thereon.[6] Sometimes the general `Sa^mkaran Vedaantist position will be referred to in tote as `SV and the Buddhist position of our two authors as `SK. The method of development will be to set forth descriptively the two causal theories in turn, and then in the third section discuss points at issue between them.

I
We may begin by noting again `Sa^mkara's basic conviction of the sole reality of Brahman, This must never be forgotten in anything which `Sa^m-

p.119

kara says, for his only concern, whatever he discusses, is to establish the truth of this conviction and chart the way to realize its liberating power. (This is really his only concern with causality at all.) As to the ultimate nature of Brahman, nothing descriptive can be said. It is the Absolute; and to attribute qualities to it is to deny its absoluteness. Sometimes it is spoken of as sat-cit-aananda (Being-Knowledge-Bliss) in one indissoluble distinctionless unity. Yet, even such language is dubious and tends to reduce ultimate Brahman to something less.

Nevertheless, there exists in some sense a phenomenal world-order also, one of distinction, of manyness, even though in the final analysis it is an illusory dream-fiction. And, if Brahman is truly the only reality it must in some way be related to this phenomenal world-order. For, as noted above, even the phenomenal order possesses its ephemeral illusory being only by sharing somehow in the being of Brahman. Hence, the problem of problems for `Sa^mkara (and Advaita) is to relate Brahman to "its" world, unity to multiplicity, non-acting being to acting being, purity to impurity, bliss to agony, knowledge to ignorance.

`Sa^mkara's basic device for doing this is the concept of material causality, though, as we shall see, he is somewhat inconsistent and irregular in the use of his analogies. His variability in this respect may be accounted for by the difficulties intrinsic in the concept when applied to the metaphysical situation as he sees it. Yet, his basic conviction of one changeless, distinctionless reality (Brahman) drives him inevitably to material-causal imagery, even though he often implies or uses other concepts and observes that none of the ordinary causal concepts which are applicable to the phenomenal world apply to the Brahman-world relation.[7]

Let us, then, observe `Sa^mkara's conception of material causality. The making of jugs from clay and ornaments from gold ore or the production of curds from milk provide good examples. Thus, clay as material cause underlies, and is more basic than, all of its modifications such as jugs. One effect or modification may take the place of another, but that does not destroy the basic clay-substance present through all of them.[8] "It is in the presence of the clay only that a pot is seen to exist."[9] The effects of a material cause, or its modifications, are found "potentially" in the cause--curds in milk, earrings in gold ore, jugs in lumps of clay. Or, in the same way, rice and barley are potentially in the earth as their material cause.[10] And to "know" a mate-

p.120

rial cause, such as clay in jugs, is to "know" all things of clayey or earthy substance.[11]

What, then, of the forces or factors ("accidental causes") that bring potentiality into actuality? With `Sa^mkara, they play a subordinate role. Thus, the curd-potentiality of milk is "merely accelerated by heat, etc."[12] Heat (and other accidental causes) only brings out the true nature of the original substance.[13] In a manner of speaking, material causes such as clay and gold lie dormantly "expecting" accidental causes to "excite" their activity.[14]

With this agrees the generalized `SV language about the relation of cause and effect. The effect "is but only a particular special condition of the cause."[15] It is held that "cause and its effects are non-different from each other."[16] Another (and favorite `SV) example of this is the waves and foam which are non-different from their cause, the ocean of water, even though separate as modifications.[17] A man is not different men by virtue of taking different positions from time to time.[18] It may be noted in passing that it is, of course, this substantial and enduring causal concept that `SK most vigorously attack.

Such, then, is the `SV version of material causality. It represents a continuing identity of substance in the "cause" and "effect" conditions of the item in question. The accidental causes work upon or modify this basic material. Now, how does this apply, if it does even by analogy, to Brahman's relation to the phenomenal world? And here we come to the nub of `Sa^mkara's conceptual difficulties and to instances of inconsistency. For certainly substantial clay is much more recognizably like its "effects" than the distinctionless Absolute is like its supposed modifications in the phenomenal world.

Brahman must indeed be placed beyond all desire to create, for such desire would introduce a "tormentor and tormented" tension into Brahman's distinctionless oneness.[19] Hence, in this context the creative potency, perhaps as both accidental and material causes, is placed outside Brahman in maayaa. Maayaa, of course, is the world-, individual-producing result of nescience

p.121

(avidyaa). Brahman is held to be "always in association with the great maayaa,"[20] and there are those in later Vedaanta who attributed to maayaa the substance of the world, i.e., its material causality.[21] Yet, the flavor of such passages as the last one seems often to be that of the imposition by avidyaa of its illusory categories, much in the manner of accidental causes, upon the basic "substance" of Brahman, the "material" cause, as false being-concepts parasitically living on true being.

In other passages, `Sa^mkara suggests a more active role for Brahman. Its "causal" relation to the world is analogous to an inactive magnet, which induces" activity without itself being active. "So the Self of all, omniscient and omnipotent, may, even though He Himself is without any such tendency, still induce such activity in everything."[22] Later in this passage it is suggested that Brahman as intelligence is indeed the prime causal factor. Or, to use a somewhat different vocabulary, Brahman is like the sun and moon, which remain themselves unaffected by the reflections which they "cause" in a pool of water,[23] or like a crystal unaffected essentially by a red color reflected into it by a nearby cotton pad.[24] Yet, again Brahman is said to "participate in limiting adjuncts," whose source is avidyaa.[25] But it must be repeated that Brahman, though "participating," is not thereby changed or affected in its essential nature. It is a kind of "general causality" like the rain which helps "cause" rice and barley growth. But rice and barley (types of sentient individuals) both have "their own different individual actions as the cause" of their diversity, and, of course, of their sins and sufferings.[26] Now and again the stock textual answer that puts the creative impulse onto second-level, or conditioned, Sagu.na Brahman, in the form of Ii`svara or God, is accepted. Such creation is that of sportive play.

It must be said that `Sa^mkara, even when speaking of ultimate Brahman, wishes somehow to keep the creative initiative with this "One without a second," the Real within the real. Negatively, Brahman is "eternally free, has no duties either to perform anything beneficial or not to perform anything unbeneficial"[27]-which leaves it free from "coercion" by maayaa Brahman--here called the Lord in somewhat anthropomorphic language--may choose to work or not to work.[28] In other words, maayaa is not coeval with

p.122

Brahman in the ultimate sense; avidyaa cannot force Brahman into world-making.

And what of the reality of this phenomenal world? Does the fact that Brahman "enters into" (i.e., shares in the increase and decrease of) its own creation,[29] participates in it, that the world is pre-existent in the Creative self,[30] render it substantial in any real sense? Not ultimately. Foam and waves upon the ocean are of the ocean, and reflections in pools and color in crystals have a certain reality, but no ultimate being. They may disappear (Or be withdrawn, to change the figure) into their source without affecting that source, just as a spider draws its web back into itself,[31] as metals are re- absorbed into the earth, or as a magician destroys his empty illusionist effects at will and without remainder, and without change in himself.[32] The phenomenal world of Brahman's modifications does "not exist in the real sense," for "if there were genuine otherness [from Brahman] it could not be known."[33] Yet, the world is not pure nothingness, for Brahman-with-world seems to be somewhat more than Brahman-without-world. Brahman may be said to "increase and decrease" with its limiting adjuncts, i.e., as there are and are not worlds. So, also, the world itself does not completely disappear (the eternality of maayaa?):

The creation, when it comes to be annihilated or dissolved, still retains that residuary potentiality, and this same potentiality is the root-cause of its regeneration, otherwise there would result the predicament of a result occurring without a cause.[34]

And on one occasion `Sa^mkara suggests that there may be a latent self-quality, or sensibility, i.e., Brahman-quality, even in the non-sentient material world itself.[35]

We may now draw our threads together. The forces at work in `Sa^mkara's philosophy of causation are obvious. Fundamental is the primacy of Brahman as the ultimate real, in terms of which `Sa^mkara must relate and describe all else--if only to prove that the ultimate real is the only real. His reverence for the scriptures, traditional Hindu that he is, sometimes impedes his philosophical thrust, however. For therein he finds some anthropomorphic language-in speaking of the "cause" of the world in particular. Hence, he is willing to adapt himself to this language on occasion in considering Ii`svara to be the creator of the world; this usage serves to maintain Brahman, even

p.123

in conditioned form, in its supremacy, if not ultimacy.[35a] Further, he maintains the superiority of Brahman to maayaa in a primordial sense, at least implicity. Maayaa, as an avidyaa-product, logically may seem to be operationally almost as necessary as Brahman to world production; but "in the beginning," or at the highest hierarchical level, Brahman is one without a second. Beside it this poor phenomenal world and maayaa itself are merest illusion.

Yet, the only reality possessed by this world (of evanescent foam, waves, and reflections) is that of Brahman (ocean and sun), which in some sense "causes" the world. How better express this than by the analogy of material causality? The revered scriptural teachings, despite Upani.sadic spiritualizing of their themes, plus `Sa^mkara's own similar efforts, often seem to have an underlying substance-philosophy. And, by analogy at least, substance-philosophy, in the form of material causality, can best serve `Sa^mkara's conviction that Brahman is ultimately all the being that is, the transcendental ground of the phenomenal world. For, as noted above, the illusory being of this world rests upon Brahman-being for even its capacity to be an illusion. Hence, unlike as the essentiality of clayness to pots may seem to be to Brahman's relation to the phenomenal world, there is a basic fittingness of analogy here that `Sa^mkara always reverts to and that accords well with his conviction of the "non-difference" of seemingly diverse causes and effects.

II.
The basic unit of phenomenal existence for `SK is what Stcherbatsky calls the point-instant.[35b] Existent reality is here-newness. What is is somewhere perceptible in space, "here" for observation--though `SK deny that space is a separate and eternal entity. It is "now" In experience. Point-instantaneousness is the mode of experience of reality, and the point-instant is the bearer (potentially) of all true knowledge of that reality as perceived by the senses. For "Sense-perception is free from conceptual content and not erroneous."[36] Yet, also, in mystical noumenal manner, `SK note that " all 'Specific Peculiarity' is, by its very nature, beyond the reach of verbal expression."[37] And it is of the essence of these entities to be "never really cognised."[38]

It should be stressed that point-instants are clearly only in the temporal

p.124

now. `SK hold there are no such things as "permanent," "enduring," or "eternal" realities. At least, such cannot enter into the dynamism of the causal order, and consequently are so existentially irrelevant as to be unreal. For to be real in the phenomenal sense is to appear; appearance in time-space contexts is the way in which an entity achieves its self-essence.[39] Yet, real appearance is only momentary, and momentary in the strictest sense. The instant at which the reality-point exists, i.e., appears, is knife-edge and needle-point in its newness. There are no parts, previous or future, to such an instant.

Now, if points exist only at instants of no "thickness," we have here a very marked and obvious atomism. And, indeed, `SK accept temporal atomism to the full. Relations, connections, unities are radically denied on every hand. ". . . when an entity comes into existence, it does so in its complete form,"[40] with no hooks, tails, or leftover connections of any sort. "Things of the nature of Individuals cannot become inter-related among themselves" because of differences of time and place and mode of action.[41] Thus, a whirling firebrand gives the impression of a circle of fire, but it is "really" only a chain of instantaneous particular fire-moments.[42] "In fact . .. there is no continuity of the slightest trace of any part of anything at a11."[43]

If all universals and continuities of any sort are non-existent, how can the Buddhist have a theory of causality? The theory can be stated both positively and negatively. Negatively, it may be stated as the flat denial that there can be a permanent or enduring cause, that is, a cause which lasts beyond the knife-edge moment of its appearance and causal efficacy, or one which has existed, even "potentially" or partially, before its moment of appearance-efficacy. To be a cause--indeed to be "existent," for all existents are causes --consists only in momentary appearance. What, then, of the relation or connection of one causal point-instant to the effected point-instant? Perhaps "contact" is the best word to employ.

Let it be repeated that the `SK viewpoint is most insistent that there is absolutely no temporal overflow or splicing of causally connected point-instants. The "cause" is non-existent until it "causes." Then it turns into its effect. Or, to state it more Buddhistically, the effect is the "destruction" of the cause; the two are mutually exclusive, save that they make temporal (and probably spatial) "contact." And the essence of the causal relation is precisely

p.125

this self-destroying succession; only if this is the case, says the Buddhist, does the cause-effect terminology have any meaning.

In this situation, the only existent is moment two of any three moments of the causal series, i.e., the present moment. It is caused by moment one, the past moment; and in turn causes moment three, the future moment; but exists in neither of them, in either part or whole. Interestingly enough, this radically atomistic theory, which denies all connections and relationships save that of temporal (and spatial?) contact, thereby becomes almost completely relational. The only reality is the relation of temporal succession; and every point-instant is both cause and effect at the same time, i.e., it is composed of relationships.

But, of course, for `SK the seeming duality of being cause and effect at once is only one of viewpoint, not of real relation, which is a one-to-one sequence. And to all those who, like `SV, would strengthen and multiply connective tissues in this area, by terms like "productivity," "potentiality," "causal relation," or "operation," `SK would reply: You have not grasped our point. To exist, i.e., to be present in the causal order, implies in the action of existing, both arising and ceasing. One facet is as essential to existence as the other. Destruction is an integral characteristic of existence; being includes non-being in its essence. Arising, or production, has non-being as a presupposition; and experience teaches that everything which arises likewise passes away. "'Destruction'. is not-different from the Thing itself; as the positive Thing is produced from its own cause."[44] `SK go on somewhat ambiguously to warn against the reification of "destruction of things" into an entity, since the term means only "the 'Dissociation of a particular form' and not the negation of its existence"[45]--which sounds suspiciously like the `SV interpretation of causality as only the gradual change of qualities or aspects of an underlying substance, so vigorously denied by `SK elsewhere.[46] This points to some final considerations as to the basic dissimilarities of the two views, but here we need only reiterate the radical intention of `SK. "It is efficiency (for effective action) that constitutes the characteristic of (existing) 'Things.' "[47] "All that the expression 'Being' (Existence) is meant to convey is only the idea of 'capacity for action.' "[48] "The momentary existence of a thing consists merely in its being produced from its cause. If a thing did so exist [beyond its momentariness] it would never cease to exist."[49]

p.126

The italicized phrases mirror the Buddhist feat of Hindu doctrines of permanence, to which we must return later.

In short, `SK's philosophy of causality might be stated simply in terms of invariable temporal succession, nothing more. Thus stated, "causality" means only that A is followed by B is followed by C, ad infinitum--which is also the Buddhist description of existence, of course. But what, then, is A, the causal "unit"? Apparently nothing more than a simplistic point-instant. That is, only point-instants can be causal, because they alone are real. Holistic entities are always suspect for `SK, because compounded entities are the work of the (false) conceptualizing intelligence, and therefore cannot be causal. Any such entity as "milk-with-tendency-to-produce-curds''--often hidden in the apparently simple concept of "milk" by people like `SV--has no real nature; for the real "nature of the Thing itself . . . is entirely free from all restrictive adjuncts."[50] (This sounds much like `SV's Brahman, but is here used only to simplify false and composite wholes. ) Nor can the human body be the cause of consciousness, because it is not a whole of a unitary sort.[51] Apparently for `SK, in the physical area, causality works only at the atomic level, though mental states may offer a different problem.

A second observation and question: `SK have no use for "causal potency" or the presence of the effect in the cause, as maintained by `SV. Causes must spring fully formed, in all their perfection as causes, into instantaneous existence. Before causes are causing they are non-existent. "When your cause is there in its perfect form, and yet there is non-existence (of its effect) while something else is existent, it is spoken of as antagonism."[52] Or, otherwise stated, it is a contradiction in terms, and existentially impossible. For a non-acting cause is not a cause at all. "What is capable of effective action is said to be 'existent,'--other than that it is said to be 'non-existent'; the two cannot exist together in the same substratum. . . ."[53]

What, then, do `SK mean in speaking of "latent causality" as they do? Presumably this: When a mental impression or physical action occurs, it sets in motion various causal chains of a "similar" sort which scatter in their various causally determined paths, combining with other causal chains (of point-instant simples) to produce new complexes when time and place ate right. (For `SK suggest that time and place determine causal conjunction, even though they may not be entities in themselves.[54]) When a cause is said 

p.127

to be "latent," therefore, it is only a way of speaking. It means only the capacity of any given causal unit to join together in a certain way with another unit when time and place make the conjunction possible.

But again we ask: What connective tissue is there between the atomistically conceived point-instants of causal reality or existence? To the meaning of "contact" between cause and effect--and `SV fears that in the Buddhist scheme any cause might produce any effect whatsoever, and hence chaos--we shall turn in the final section. But here we may note some other factors of continuity hinted at by `SK. There is the suggestion at various places that there is an independent real order of events and qualities which produces order in the perceptions of the beholder. For all differentiation there must be something "in the Idea (or Cognition) itself which appertains specifically to each object envisaged by it."[55] In view of another statement about the "formlessness" of all cognitions as such, the implication is clearly that the external order gives form and order to cognition.[56]

Yet, what is it that the cognizer cognizes in the external world? Point-instants--the true reals--or only partially false conceptualized wholes? There is no clear answer in `SK; the verdict seems mixed. For example: Himalaya does "not differ with time and place" but its atoms "are diverse and momentary."[57] Thus, the point-instant atoms composing Himalaya, even though obviously non-perceptual, are yet held to be the true reals in theory. But the mass, Himalaya, which is what is perceived--though it ought to be a false conceptual whole--continues "permanently." Is, then, the perception of Himalaya false? In any case, we seem to have, contrary to Buddhist principles, perception producing a false conceptual wholeness, an empty eternal form, and conception producing the real, intuitively (?) "perceived" atoms.

Lastly, the question of the relation of the causal and cognitional series must be raised. Are they independently real, or mutually causative or dependent? `SK seem to consider the mental series independently real--unless we consider mental states to include a bodily factor. After denying that body is the continuing cause of cognitions, `SK assert that one conscious state is the "material cause" of the succeeding one, i.e., there is no outside, other-than-cognitional, factor involved.[58] And the situation is the same between rebirths as between conscious moments in one life.[59] So, also, each mental, i.e., personal, series is internal to itself.[60] Just conceivably the body may be

p.128

considered a point-instant factor in the mental series, or mental states include a bodily factor--though this is by no means clear--so that the personal causal series might be a psychosomatic one. In view of the false wholeness of body, however, body-mind wholeness seems even more questionable. Indeed, the mental series more often seems to be in the observer's role, apart from the physical series. Yet, again ambiguously, the mind of the saint can transform his bodily particles into any desired shape or form, according to Buddhist orthodoxy.

The temporal relation of cognition and event, referred to in the `SV context above, is also of interest. In some places, `SK seem to make a clear statement that the event causes its cognition:

... it is not possible for any causal relation to subsist between synchronous things. What does not exist could have no previous potentiality, and it could have no use later on; all causes must exist before (these effects); hence the object caused cannot exist along with its own cognition.[61]

But this then raises the problem far the Buddhist: What is it that is cognized? For, since event-instant does not remain static but immediately changes into its effect, what is known in the resulting cognition is the effect, not the cause. Thus, cognition is always one step behind the causal flow and is false. Indeed, on Buddhist grounds how can it be cognized at all?

Though `SK never speak to this point, implicit here may be that same perception-cum-event, or event-cum-perception, assumption often present in Indian philosophy by which subject-object consciousness is one unitary, simultaneous event. Cognition may not require any time; we may have the occurrence only of "cognized-event." So, also, Stcherbatsky implies with regard to the Buddhist scholar Vasubandhu in his Abhidharmako`sa:

We read in scripture, "Consciousness apprehends." What is consciousness here meant to do?
Nothing at all. It simply appears in coordination with its objective elements, like a result that is homogeneous with its cause.[62]

One other suggestion is to the point. Contemporary Southern Buddhism speaks of the mental point-instants (mental moments) as much more rapidly pulsed than the material point-instants. If there were several moments of consciousness set over against one moment of material occurrence, this would provide a sense of the continuing similarity of apprehension of "enduring" physical forms. Whether the 17 component elements of the one mental instant represent each in itself a unit of awareness, or must be taken to-

p.129

gether to achieve awareness, is not clear. However, presumably even the 17 taken together are shorter in their totality than one physical-event pulsation.

And which order, mental or physical, is the more real? It may be that there is implied only one order with physical and mental poles, as the perceptual situation seems to suggest. However, one passage speaks in phenomenalistic terms in asserting that non-existence means that an event, " (prior to production)... is not found to fulfill the conditions of Cognizability,"[63] i.e., things do not exist unless they are cognizable. (Conceivably, a buddha could know many things not open to human intelligence, of course, thus opening up the possibility of many humanly unverifiable existences.) And another passage seems to suggest an "esse est percipi" doctrine :

... all diversity of the nature of things comes out of a series of "ideas" bringing the things into existence; like the "burning capacity" of fire; as a matter of fact, they come into existence every moment, as endowed with diverse potentialities, through the functioning of the series of ideas coming one after the other.[64]

But what are these "things" thus brought into existence by the power of successive cognitions? Obviously not the truly real point-instants which are beyond ordinary perception--though we do have a rough approximation of their rapid changeability in our conscious awareness of change even in perceptual entities. Perhaps the "things" which are brought into existence are these pseudo-realities, point-instants bound together by false conceptualization into specious wholes such as "burning capacity of fire." They may be analogous to the "secondary" qualities of Western philosophy, added to the "primary" ones by the form of human awareness. With regard to these "things," we may have a perceptual realism as suggested in this passage:

It is the form (aspect) of the Thing itself that is held to be "differentiated"; it is in that same form that it exists, and it is in this form that it is perceived.[65]

Or we may wish to go as far as Stcherbatsky does with reference to Vasubandhu :

The question of the reality of an outer world is, strictly speaking, obviated. In a system which denies the existence of a personality, splits everything into a plurality of separate elements, and admits of no real interaction between them, there is no possibility of distinguishing between an external and internal world. The latter does not exist, all elements are equally external towards one another.[66] 

p.130

In conclusion of this section, it is of interest to note that just as the `SV tradition believes that it saves man by positing an unchangeable order of Selfhood, that of Brahman-Aatman, so the `SK view holds, in precise opposition, that the doctrine of momentariness presents man's only hope for salvation. To the latter, permanent Self (or selves) means that man, even the universe itself, would be a prisoner of its present state, for all change would be unreal. Contrarily, the doctrine that no two moments in the causal series are bridged over by any connective identity, but only held together by "contact, is a doctrine of hope built into the very nature of things themselves. In fact, it suggests not only a theory of causality, but a methodology of salvation: The insertion of discrimination's knife edge between two consecutive moments, recognizing their absolute difference from each other, is a means of cutting that causal chain of successive impressions called variously "sameness," "identity," "self." This knife edge of insight may expand its tiny crevice into an eternal boundless here-newness that dissipates all deterministic succession that binds man to his present unsaved selfhood, and may free him ultimately from existence itself. Or, if the causal series be conceived as a two-dimensional linear progression, a third-dimensional, quite other, direction can be taken. Thus, by the very recognition and appropriation of the inmost atomistic nature of causal relations, their power can be escaped.

III.
How, then, shall we summarize and characterize the basic conflict of viewpoints between `SV and `SK? The `SV objection to `SK Buddhism can be stated as follows: Momentariness, in which there is only something called "contact" between cause and effect, temporal-spatial contiguity, is insufficient to guarantee the integrity of the cause-effect relation. That is, one could not guarantee that any one result rather than any other would follow from a given cause.

Such a "universe" would be one of intellectual and moral chaos for `SV. Indeed, there could not be an organized universe wherein lotuses might indiscriminately produce elephants as well as lotuses, or what have you. And how can man follow any enduring or certain course of action leading to salvation in such chaos? There must be some similarity, permanence, or partial identity which passes on from cause to effect, or is present in both, to provide the necessary continuity.

Not so, say `SK. You have misunderstood our argument. You make our causal contact into causal gap, from which anything may come. But we hold

p.131

to the binding character of the contact between causal moments in the causal series. "Contact" is not a thing in itself, to be sure, but it does guarantee the passage of the appropriate cause into the appropriate effect. Lotuses do not produce elephants in our world, either. Location in time and space and perhaps the factor of similarity (see below, p. 133) are of sufficient strength to provide the necessary continuity for a phenomenal world.

`SK, in their turn, mercilessly attack the concept of a "permanent," i.e., continuously acting, cause mercilessly. For `SK, anything that endures beyond one moment, any point that lasts more than an instant, is for all practical purposes eternal. For, if it crosses one temporal divide unchanged, it is no longer part of the temporal series, but, like featureless, ineffective, eternal space, is beyond and above the series. And perhaps we have here a key to understanding the fundamental quality of the `SV-`SK controversy. `SV is essentially space-substance oriented, but `SK are essentially time-succession oriented. Hence, they clash at almost all points. The space-substance orientation of `SV appears at every turn. Substance, the root of the material-causality concept, is, of course, spatial; certainly it does not belong to the
realm of restless temporal succession. Indeed, Brahman, the ultimate reality, is often spoken of as manifest in, or like, eternal space. Furthermore, logical relations are always more fundamental to `SV than temporal ones. Perhaps in some sense `SK are correct when they accuse `SV's permanent causality of being productive of a non-temporal synchronous universe in which all change is sheer illusion.

`SK Buddhism is, of course, precisely the opposite. It feels keenly the existential reality of time and embodies it in its philosophy at every point. `SK do, indeed, deny the concept of time as a thing--because it would then be a static eternal non-entity---but only the better to embody "real" time integrally in theory and practice:

On account of their [i.e., qualified states'] coming into existence in succession ... the whole phenomenon is regulated by Time, not by the conditions of any Quality [67]

And, of course, in consonance with time as being of the essence of causal change, `SK look everywhere for discontinuities, difference within sameness, evanescence, and irregularities. Indeed, the only type of causality which makes any sense to them is precisely the arising-and-perishing, the changing-into-effect, efficient cause.

For `SK, whatever has the semblance of eternally unchanging space or substance is also non-existent, or at least does not affect existence in the

p.132

slightest. It is an empty concept having no effective role in the dynamic temporal order of experience and perception. And so, for `SK, a "permanent cause" is a contradiction in terms:

For us, eternal things cannot produce any effects, because "consecutive" and "concurrent" action are mutually contradictory; and if objects are consecutive, there must be the same consecutiveness in their cognitions also. . . .

... only non-eternal things can be productive causes; as it is these alone which go on unceasingly changing their sequential character--of being present now and past at the next moment.[68]

Indeed, say `SK, if causes were "permanent," i.e., in continuing or continuous activity, the total universe would be temporally static, produced all at once. For, when a "cause" is present, the "effect" must come at once:

That which is itself devoid of birth [i.e., two-moment eternal things] cannot be the cause of anything.... Otherwise, all things would come into existence simultaneously.[69]

Were this the case, all change would be illusory. Man would be already saved, the universe completely perfect, consisting of eternal, "non-existent" Brahman.

But is this apparently contradictory opposition as radical as it seems? Some of it appears to be a matter of emphasis, or even of mere semantics. Obviously `SV is synthetic, holistic, stability-seeking, afraid of flux. Hence, the regularities and "permanencies" of experience-consciousness and the external world--are insisted upon. They are seen as necessary to any order of thought and life, and as manifestations of an eternal identity. Therefore, `SV give to identity and continuity dynamic causal force. Yet `SV do not wish entirely to destroy change and difference. Indeed, `SV criticized the Saa^mkhya for not having sufficient dynamism in its ontological scheme to produce the phenomenal world. And all of the `SV language of magicianship, ignorance, maayaa, limiting adjuncts of self and Self, indicate an awareness of change and evanescence, paradoxically all the more emphasized because of Brahman's eternal unchangeability.

So, also, there is a desire for sameness-in-difference, some continuity, in `SK as well as `SV. As noted above (p. 127), the physical form (perceptual or conceptual) of Himalaya does achieve some sort of permanence, even though its constituent atoms are constantly changing. Point-instants-in-themselves give reality to the phenomenal order and present a basis for the perceived succession and quality of that order. And the category of "simi-

p.133

larity" of successive states slips into the discussion of the mental or cognitional series with regard to memory. Thus:

Hence, even though, for some reason, they are cognised as being similar in form, through the presence of some similarity;--yet, in reality, their nature is entirely different. That is the reason why only one entity becomes the cause of only one other entity, and not everything of everything.[70]

Thus is "similarity" called in to save at least the mental series from that chaos of disconnection feared by `SV. To be sure, the definition of similarity as "similar in form, through the presence of some similarity," seems quite circular. The intention of `SK is quite clear, however: each remembrance is the "material cause" of the succeeding one, tied to it by "similarity," which is not a separate entity but a loose and often inaccurate relation which covers "real" diversity with the cloak of pseudo-likeness. Yet, it does cover that atomistic difference in an apparently important, even essential, way, since it is the reason "why only one entity becomes the cause of only one other entity" in the recognitional series. Indeed, in this personal cognitional chain of causal moments (the "self"),the chain is perpetuated by the "successive production of more and more specialized 'moments' by a specially vivid apprehension."[71] And what can be more tightly linked than the successive stages of one's own karmic history and identity? And perhaps, if, as Stcherbatsky puts it, the causal series is indistinguishably inner-outer all at once, the series governed by specially vivid apprehensions of similarity (and difference) may be the movement of reality itself.

This should lead us to a somewhat closer inspection of the restless temporal dynamism of `SK momentariness. Is it as atomistic and as dynamic as it seems? In fact, a considerable static element can be discerned in it. For example, there is no such thing as physical motion in `SK dynamism. The circle described by the whirling torch is not motion of anything through space, but a succession of different fire-particles or fire-states at successively different positions. No particle moves from one place to another. `SK are very specific with regard to non-motion:

When a thing ceases to exist at a certain spot it cannot subsequently get at any other spot ...; all the things in question do cease at the very spot where they come into existence. . . [72]

So, also, this implies that there is no movement from one time to another, no passing through successive instants. For point and instant cease together,

p.134

at once in the same place and time. Otherwise, there would be two-moment eternal persistence of substance. Thus:

At the moment of its existence itself it is within the clutches of disappearance (destruction); and as such is unable to pass over to the other place ... it is not possible for it to pass over even the minutest space.[73]

Thus, the only Buddhist dynamism of which we can speak within the causal order is dynamism in place and stationary time. The point-instant is self-contained, finding its own grave in the place and moment of its first and only existence. So, also, "doers" and "actions" are unreal. "Doer" is only a karmic chain, and even thus conceived is only a mere concept.[74]

This raises a final question of evaluation. In the long run, despite all the spirited dispute between the `SK and `SV traditions, are not their ultimate universes much alike? For both of them the phenomenal world is unreal, whether as seen by `SV as mere foam upon the changeless deep of Brahman, or by `SK as an endless series of point-instants firmly anchored in their places and times. Is not the integrity of the causal order as real sabotaged by both, as Naagaarjuna realized? Indeed, why the strong Buddhist distinction between empty eternal forms and dynamic causal instants? When we remember that "existence" for the Buddhist means only the evanescent causal order, which he seeks to escape with as great ardor as the Hindu Advaitist, has he really insulted the eternal realities by calling them non-existent; or is he giving them a mark of highest esteem? Is not his Nirvaa.na as empty, as eternal, and as non-active as Brahman? In fact, if one should cut Brahman's creative connection with the world, Brahman and Nirvaa.na would not be far apart conceptually. And perhaps only with difficulty can the outsider distinguish between the experiences of union with Brahman and the "going out of self" in Nirvaa.na.

Two concluding statements will vividly indicate the measure of `SV-`SK likeness in this context. The first is from `SV:

The whole universe of action, its factors and results [i.e., cause and effect], beginning with the Undifferentiated, comes within the category of ignorance.[75]

And, of course, for `SV, ignorance means the unreality of maayaa.

From `SK, the philosophers of dynamic change, comes this:

If it had been held by us that there is really a Doer and Experiencer, then the doctrine of the "Perpetual Flux" might have involved the anomaly of "the waste of what is done and the befalling of what is not done";--as a matter of fact, however,

p.135

the view held by us is that the Universe is mere Idea, and that there is nothing done or experienced by anyone.[76]

Now, it is true that the latter comment is primarily spoken against the doctrine of soul. And so one might say that it is only soul whose unreality is here in question, not that of causal sequence. But in the end there is little difference. The mind's cognitional order is not clearly distinguishable from the physical phenomenal order. The whole realm of "existence" in the Buddhist world is but a restless, tormented dream that someone--identity unspecified--is having. But, as soon as the dreamer is released into changeless Nirvaa.na, as changelessly undifferentiated as Brahman, for him all existence and causal order will disappear.

No doubt, if all dreamers were released, the total order would dissolve into that same Nirvaa.na, the only true Real. There remains then only the question as to whether the superior importance given to the ever-changing order of causal succession by the Buddhist, within the realm of ignorance, is a better psychological means of escaping the changefulness of that realm than the Hindu alternative of the realization of an Eternal Identity amid illusory phenomenal succession.

NOTES
1. Surendranath Dasgupta, A History of Indian Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1961), Vol. II, pp. 172-173.

2. Ibid., Vol. I (1922), pp. 493-494.

3. "`Sa^mkara's Arguments against the Buddhists," Philosophy East and West, III, No. 4 (January, 1954), 291-306.

4. Brahma-Suutra-Shaankara-Bhaashya, V. M. Apte, trans. (Bombay: G. R. Bhatkal, 1960).

5. B.rhadaara.nyaka Upani.sad, with commentary by `Sa^mkaaracaaraya. Swaamii Maadhavaananda, trans. (Alma; Himalayan: Advaita Ashram, 1950).

6. The Tattvasa^ngraha of `Saantarak.sita, with commentary of Kamala`siila. Vols. I, II. Ganganther Ha, trans. Volumes I, II. Gawked Oriental Series, Vols. LXXX and LXXXIII. (Abroad: Oriental Institute, 1937, 1939).

7. Brahma-Suutra, I. iv. 27, com

8. B.radar.Naka Upani.sad, I. i. 4.

9. Brahma-`Suutra, Suutra, II. i. 15, com.

10. Ibid., I. iv. 25, com.

11. Ibid., I. iv. 23, com.; II. i. 14, com.

12. Ibid., II. i. 24, com.

13. Ibid.

14. Ibid., I. iv. 23. Dr. Karl Potter writes that the term "expect" is in his opinion an exaggeration. It should be further noted in this general connection that in I. iv. 23-27 and II. i. 24-25 it is repeatedly asserted that Brahman is both material and accidental (efficient) cause of the world, i.e., containing within itself the power to modify itself (accidental causal potency) as well as being the material (or substantial?) cause of the world.

15. Ibid., II. ii. 17, com.

16. Ibid., II. i. 14, com.

17. Ibid., II. i. 13, com.

18. Ibid., II. i. 18, com.

19. Ibid., II. i. 10, com.

20. Ibid., II. ii. 4, com.

21. Dasgupta, op. cit., Vol. II, p. 11.

22. Brahma-Suutra, II. ii. 3, com.

23. B.radar.Naka Upani.sad, II. 4. 13.

24. Ibid., II. 1. 20.

25. Brahma-Suutra, III. ii. 20, 21, com.

26. Ibid., II. i. 34.

27. Ibid., II. i. 22, com.

28. Ibid., 11. ii. 5, com.

29. Ibid., II. i. 13, com.

30. Ibid., II. i. 7, com.

31. Ibid., I. iv. 27, com.

32. Ibid., II. i. 9, com.

33. B.radar.Naka Up^Annie.sad, II. 4. 6.

34. Brahma-Suutra, I. iii* 30, com.

35. Ibid., II. i. 4, com.

35a. "Supremacy" is used here to refer to a qualified or lesser form of ultimate, suitable for the phenomenal-world context.

35b. Buddhist Logic, Indo-Iranian Reprints ('S-Grabenhage: Mouton and Co., 1958),Vol. I, Part II, chap. 1.

36. Tattvasa^ngraha, Text No. 1214. Italics mine.

37. Ibid., 734.

38. Ibid., 870 and com.

39. Ibid., 32, corn.

40. Ibid., 441-443, com.

41. Ibid., 873-874.

42. Ibid., 1254-1256.

43. Ibid., 540, com.

44. Ibid., 358.

45. Ibid., 382.

46. Ibid., 31-45, passim.

47. Ibid., 415-416.

48. Ibid., 727-729.

49. Ibid., 688.

50. Ibid., 30.

51. Ibid., 1886, com.

52. Ibid., 441-443, com.

53. Ibid., 1675-1677.

54. Ibid., 115-116.

55. Ibid., 1181-1183.

56. Ibid., 533-535, com.

57. Ibid., 875.

58. Ibid., 1886-1915, passim.

59. Ibid., 1897.

60. Ibid., 1893-1896.

61. Ibid., 468, corn. Cf. ibid., 149-150, 473-474.

62. Th. Stcherbatsky, The Central Conception of Buddhism (Calcutta: S. Gupta, 1961), p. 48. Italics mine.

63. Tattvasa^ngraha, 31, com.

64. Ibid., 438, com.

65. Ibid., 1674.

66. Stcherbatsky, op. cit., p. 49.

67. Tattvasa^ngraha, 675-676, com.

68. Ibid., 76 and com.

69. Ibid., 87, com.

70. Ibid., 438, com.

71. Ibid., 543, com.

72. Ibid., 692, com.

73. Ibid., 696-697, com.

74. Ibid., 504.

75. B.rhadaara.nyaka Upani.sad, I. iii. 2.

76. Tattvasa^ngraha,538-539, com.

没有相关内容

欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn


            在线投稿

------------------------------ 权 益 申 明 -----------------------------
1.所有在佛教导航转载的第三方来源稿件,均符合国家相关法律/政策、各级佛教主管部门规定以及和谐社会公序良俗,除了注明其来源和原始作者外,佛教导航会高度重视和尊重其原始来源的知识产权和著作权诉求。但是,佛教导航不对其关键事实的真实性负责,读者如有疑问请自行核实。另外,佛教导航对其观点的正确性持有审慎和保留态度,同时欢迎读者对第三方来源稿件的观点正确性提出批评;
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。