2025婵犵數濮烽弫鍛婃叏閹绢喗鍎夊鑸靛姇缁狙囧箹鐎涙ɑ灏ù婊呭亾娣囧﹪濡堕崟顓炲闂佸憡鐟ョ换姗€寮婚敐澶婄闁挎繂妫Λ鍕磼閻愵剙鍔ゆ繛纭风節瀵鎮㈤崨濠勭Ф闂佸憡鎸嗛崨顔筋啅缂傚倸鍊烽懗鑸靛垔椤撱垹鍨傞柛顐f礀閽冪喖鏌曟繛鐐珕闁稿妫濋弻娑氫沪閸撗€妲堝銈呴獜閹凤拷4闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾剧懓顪冪€n亝鎹i柣顓炴閵嗘帒顫濋敐鍛婵°倗濮烽崑鐐烘偋閻樻眹鈧線寮撮姀鈩冩珕闂佽姤锚椤︻喚绱旈弴銏♀拻濞达綀娅g敮娑㈡煕閺冣偓濞茬喖鐛弽顓ф晝闁靛牆娲g粭澶婎渻閵堝棛澧遍柛瀣仱閹繝濡烽埡鍌滃幗闂佸搫娲ㄩ崑娑㈠焵椤掆偓濠€閬嶅焵椤掍胶鍟查柟鍑ゆ嫹23闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾剧懓顪冪€n亝鎹i柣顓炴閵嗘帒顫濋敐鍛婵°倗濮烽崑鐐烘偋閻樻眹鈧線寮撮姀鈩冩珖闂侀€炲苯澧扮紒顕嗙到铻栧ù锝堟椤旀洟姊洪悷鎵憼闁荤喆鍎甸幃姗€鍩¢崘顏嗭紲闂佺粯鐟㈤崑鎾绘煕閵娿儳鍩g€殿喖顭锋俊鎼佸煛閸屾矮绨介梻浣呵归張顒傜矙閹达富鏁傞柨鐕傛嫹 闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾剧懓顪冪€n亝鎹i柣顓炴閵嗘帒顫濋敐鍛婵°倗濮烽崑鐐烘偋閻樻眹鈧線寮撮姀鐘栄囨煕鐏炲墽鐓瑙勬礀閳规垿顢欑紒鎾剁窗闂佸憡顭嗛崘锝嗙€洪悗骞垮劚濞茬娀宕戦幘鑸靛枂闁告洦鍓涢敍娑㈡⒑閸涘⿴娈曞┑鐐诧躬閹即顢氶埀顒€鐣烽崼鏇ㄦ晢濠㈣泛顑嗗▍灞解攽閻樺灚鏆╁┑顔芥尦楠炲﹥寰勯幇顒傦紱闂佽宕橀褔鏌ㄩ妶鍡曠箚闁靛牆瀚崗宀勬煕濡粯宕屾慨濠呮閳ь剙婀辨慨鐢稿Υ閸愵亞纾奸柍褜鍓氱粭鐔煎焵椤掆偓椤曪綁骞庨懞銉ヤ簻闂佺ǹ绻楅崑鎰板储閹惧墎纾介柛灞剧懅閸斿秹鎷戞潏銊d簻闁靛鍎虫晶锕傛煛瀹€瀣?濞寸媴濡囬幏鐘诲箵閹烘繃缍嗛梻鍌欐祰椤曟牠宕伴幘璇茬9婵犻潧妫涢弳锕傛煙閻戞ê鐏嶆俊鎻掔墛閹便劌螖閳ь剙螞閺冨倹顫曢柨鐕傛嫹闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾剧懓顪冪€n亜顒㈡い鎰Г閹便劌顫滈崱妤€骞婄紓鍌氬€瑰銊╁箟缁嬫鍚嬮柛顐線缂冩洟姊虹拠鏌ヮ€楅柛妯荤矒瀹曟垿骞樼紒妯煎幈闂佸搫娲㈤崝灞剧閻愮儤鐓ユ繛鎴炵懅濞插瓨鎱ㄦ繝鍐┿仢闁诡喚鍏樺鑸垫償閹炬潙鐦辩紓鍌氬€风欢锟犲闯椤曗偓瀹曞綊宕奸弴鐐电暫闂佽法鍠撴慨鎾础閹惰姤鐓忛煫鍥ュ劤绾惧潡鏌涘Ο鍏兼毈婵﹦绮粭鐔煎炊瑜嶆导搴g磽娴e搫校闁搞劌娼¢幃浼搭敊绾拌鲸寤洪梺閫炲苯澧寸€殿喖顭烽弫鎰緞濡粯娅嶉梻浣虹帛閸ㄩ潧煤閵堝棙鍙忔繛鎴欏灪閳锋垿姊洪銈呬粶闁兼椿鍨遍弲鍫曨敊閸撗咃紳閻庡箍鍎遍幏鎴濐啅閵夈儳鏆嗛柨婵嗘椤曟粎绱掔紒妯肩畵妞ゎ偅绻堥、妤呭磼閵堝懏鏆╅梻鍌氬€峰ù鍥р枖閺囥垹闂柨鏇炲€哥粻顖炴煥閻曞倹瀚�3闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾剧懓顪冪€n亝鎹i柣顓炴閵嗘帒顫濋敐鍛婵°倗濮烽崑鐐烘偋閻樻眹鈧線寮撮姀鈩冩珕闂佽姤锚椤︻喚绱旈弴銏♀拻濞达綀娅g敮娑㈡煕閺冣偓濞茬喖鐛弽顓ф晝闁靛牆娲g粭澶婎渻閵堝棛澧遍柛瀣仱閹繝濡烽埡鍌滃幗闂佸搫娲ㄩ崑娑㈠焵椤掆偓濠€閬嶅焵椤掍胶鍟查柟鍑ゆ嫹26闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾剧懓顪冪€n亝鎹i柣顓炴閵嗘帒顫濋敐鍛婵°倗濮烽崑鐐烘偋閻樻眹鈧線寮撮姀鈩冩珖闂侀€炲苯澧扮紒顕嗙到铻栧ù锝堟椤旀洟姊洪悷鎵憼闁荤喆鍎甸幃姗€鍩¢崘顏嗭紲闂佺粯鐟㈤崑鎾绘煕閵娿儳鍩g€殿喖顭锋俊鎼佸煛閸屾矮绨介梻浣呵归張顒傜矙閹达富鏁傞柨鐕傛嫹
您现在的位置:佛教导航>> 五明研究>> 英文佛教>>正文内容

Early Advaita Vedaanta and Buddhism

       

发布时间:2009年04月18日
来源:不详   作者:Richard King
人关注  打印  转发  投稿


·期刊原文


Early Advaita Vedaanta and Buddhism: The Mahaayaana Context of the Gau.dapaadiiya-Kaarikaa

By Richard King

Reviewed by Arvind Sharma

Philosophy East & West

V. 48 No. 4 (October 1998) pp. 661-663

Copyright 1998 by University of Hawaii Press


 

p.661

The Gau.dapaadiiya-Kaarikaa (GK) is widely regarded as one of the earliest statements of what subsequently became the well-known school of Advaita Vedaanta. Scholarship in this century has been active on three main issues surrounding it: (1) when it was composed and by whom, (2) whether it is a unitary or a composite work, and (3) to what extent it has been influenced by Buddhism. The three issues are obviously interrelated, but each deserves recognition in its own right. Richard King's Early Advaita Vedaanta and Buddhism bears on all three, identifying the last as its gravitational center of interest.

The author's conclusions are that the text "is pre-`Sa^nkarite since it shows no evidence of any influences in the post-sixth-century era" and in all probability is not from the hand of Gau.dapaada (p. 36); that it is a composite work; and that "all four prakara.nas display evidence of Buddhist influence" (p. 236). It is in identifying the nature of the influences on the text that the author makes a distinct advance. He specifies the nature of these influences textually in terms of each prakara.na (p. 236), and also tries to spell them out in terms of the two main philosophical schools of Mahaayaana Buddhism in India--the Madhyamaka and the Yogaacaara.

King's analysis of how Madhyamaka Buddhism and Advaita Vedaanta turn in different directions while arriving at the same crossroads is particularly lucid. The crossroads are the "inconsistencies of the common sense notions of duality and change" (p. 126), succinctly identified by Bradley as follows: "something, A, changes, and therefore it cannot be permanent. On the other hand, if A is not permanent, what is it that changes?" (p. 129).

[In this debate] over the status of object (A) and its various modes or states of manifestation (X', X2, X3, etc.) the Buddhist accepts the empirical efficacy of changes in states but does not accept the independent reality of the possessor of these states (A). This is the doctrine of the no-self which rejects such


 

p.662

notions as mentally fabricated reifications (prapannca). In Advaita Vedaanta (A) is accepted and it is the manifested states that are denied ultimate reality since reality cannot change. Thus, both the Madhyamaka and Gau.dapaadian Advaita derive their positions from the logical dichotomy between an entity and change.... [B]oth as it were grasp separate "horns" of the dilemma.... (pp. 130-131)

The clear recognition of this distinction enables the author to be more precise in pinpointing both the Buddhist influence and its limitation in the context of Advaita Vedaanta, as when it is pointed out that the Gau.dapaadian doctrine of non-origination (ajativaada) "is dependent upon the Madhyamaka understanding of the non-arising (anutpaada) of dharmas" (p. 237). The author admits the conclusion is not novel but it acquires clear content in his hands, when he explains:

Both the Gau.dapaadian doctrine of non-origination and the text's belief that it is not in conflict with any other view are drawn from an absolutistic (mis)reading of Naagaarjuna's arguments in the MMK. The GK takes Naagaarjuna's rejection of all views (d.r.s.ti) as incipient forms of absolutism and adopts it for its own purposes. All views, the authors of the GK argue, entail an unoriginated absolute. This is seen as the final vindication of ajaativaada. (p. 237)

At the same time, the limitation is suggested by the fact "that the prima facie similarity of Advaita and Mahaayaana ideas, in actuality, reflects their direct incommensurability" (p. 238). So far as Madhyamaka Mahaayaana is concerned, the two schools of Advaita and Madhyamaka "reach a philosophical impasse precisely over the question of 'Svabhaava: Ni.hsvabhaava' " (p. 237).

Turning next to Yogaacaara Buddhism: the "discussions of the equality of dream and waking states" and "the doctrine of non-duality (advaya) of consciousness -- i.e. the denial of the validity of subject-object divisions in experience" are identified as "Yogaacaara-inspired themes" (p. 236). Indeed, it is asserted that "the ontological denial of origination (ajaati-vaada) on the one hand and the epistemological denial of subject-object duality (advaya-vaada) on the other, found in the Gau.dapaadiiya-Kaarikaa" are dependent upon the "Madhyamaka in the case of the former and the Yogaacaara in the case of the latter" (p. 203).

Not only are the streams of influence clearly identified in terms of the two schools, but it is also suggested that there are even other influences at work not noticed earlier on account of the "philosophically narrow and historically misleading assumption that the Madhyamaka and Yogaacaara schools are the only Mahaayaana influences" (p. 240) on the text under review. According to the author, this "reflects an inadequate grasp of the absolutistic: non-absolutistic divide between Advaita Vedaanta and scholastic Mahaayaana on the one hand, and a failure to appreciate the diversity of Mahaayaana (encompassing absolutistic


 

p.663

approaches also) on the other" (p. 240), especially as "certain pre-Gau.dapaadian texts of the Mahaayaana tradition ... appear at times to uphold a form of ontological absolutism akin to the doctrines."

It is difficult to claim conclusiveness in such contested matters, but the nuanced arguments are here presented with admirable philosophical and historical sophistication and in the light of previous and existing scholarship in the field. This book, which also has a translation of the MK appended to it, is therefore to be highly commended.

Occasionally, however, hints of over-enthusiasm seep through like a slow water leak. For instance, the writer holds the author(s) of the GK guilty of the "imposition of an absolutistic ontology onto the mainstream (non-absolutistic) philosophical texts of the Mahaayaana and Yogaacaara schools" (p. 241). Would it not be more accurate to accuse the author(s) of the GK of deriving an absolutistic ontology from the aforementioned texts rather than imposing it on them? In fact, is any kind of accusation really in order? Does the GK claim to present the Buddhist point of view? One may accuse it of using Buddhist grist for its Advaita mill, but Advaita does the same to the Vedic texts. The quest for truth in Hinduism is notoriously source-blind. Christianity appropriates the basic scripture of Judaism, imparts to it its own spin, and then proceeds to use it against Judaism. Christianity could then be accused of imposing its own interpretation on Judaism, but this is a far cry from what the author of the GK is doing with Buddhist ideas. The point, briefly, is that a preoccupation with historical influences may blind one to the existential obviousness of certain procedures. For instance, Natalia Isayeva wondered during the course of an international seminar on Dharma held in July 1997 at the Indian Institute of Advanced Study in Shimla, India, whether the differences in the texture of the four prakara.nas in the GK may not reflect the existential differences in the four states of consciousness dealt with in the GK. -- Worth a thought?


没有相关内容

欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn


            在线投稿

------------------------------ 权 益 申 明 -----------------------------
1.所有在佛教导航转载的第三方来源稿件,均符合国家相关法律/政策、各级佛教主管部门规定以及和谐社会公序良俗,除了注明其来源和原始作者外,佛教导航会高度重视和尊重其原始来源的知识产权和著作权诉求。但是,佛教导航不对其关键事实的真实性负责,读者如有疑问请自行核实。另外,佛教导航对其观点的正确性持有审慎和保留态度,同时欢迎读者对第三方来源稿件的观点正确性提出批评;
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。