2025濠电姷鏁告慨鐑藉极閸涘﹥鍙忛柟缁㈠枟閸庡顭块懜闈涘缂佺嫏鍥х閻庢稒蓱鐏忣厼霉濠婂懎浜惧ǎ鍥э躬婵″爼宕熼鐐差瀴闂備礁鎲¢悷銉ф崲濮椻偓瀵鏁愭径濠勵吅闂佹寧绻傚Λ顓炍涢崟顓犵<闁绘劦鍓欓崝銈嗙箾绾绡€鐎殿喖顭烽幃銏ゅ川婵犲嫮肖闂備礁鎲¢幐鍡涘川椤旂瓔鍟呯紓鍌氬€搁崐鐑芥嚄閼搁潧鍨旀い鎾卞灩閸ㄥ倿鏌涢锝嗙闁藉啰鍠栭弻鏇熺箾閻愵剚鐝曢梺绋款儏濡繈寮诲☉姘勃闁告挆鈧Σ鍫濐渻閵堝懘鐛滈柟鍑ゆ嫹4闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁惧墽鎳撻—鍐偓锝庝簼閹癸綁鏌i鐐搭棞闁靛棙甯掗~婵嬫晲閸涱剙顥氬┑掳鍊楁慨鐑藉磻閻愮儤鍋嬮柣妯荤湽閳ь兛绶氬鎾閳╁啯鐝曢梻浣藉Г閿氭い锔诲枤缁辨棃寮撮姀鈾€鎷绘繛杈剧秬濞咃絿鏁☉銏$厱闁哄啠鍋撴繛鑼枛閻涱噣寮介褎鏅濋梺闈涚墕濞诧絿绮径濠庢富闁靛牆妫涙晶閬嶆煕鐎n剙浠遍柟顕嗙節婵$兘鍩¢崒婊冨箺闂備礁鎼ú銊╁磻濞戙垹鐒垫い鎺嗗亾婵犫偓闁秴鐒垫い鎺嶈兌閸熸煡鏌熼崙銈嗗24闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁惧墽鎳撻—鍐偓锝庝簼閹癸綁鏌i鐐搭棞闁靛棙甯掗~婵嬫晲閸涱剙顥氬┑掳鍊楁慨鐑藉磻閻愮儤鍋嬮柣妯荤湽閳ь兛绶氬鎾閳╁啯鐝栭梻渚€鈧偛鑻晶鎵磼椤曞棛鍒伴摶鏍归敐鍫燁仩妞ゆ梹娲熷娲偡閹殿喗鎲奸梺鑽ゅ枂閸庣敻骞冨鈧崺锟犲礃椤忓棴绱查梻浣虹帛閻熴垽宕戦幘缁樼厱闁靛ǹ鍎抽崺锝団偓娈垮枛椤攱淇婇幖浣哥厸闁稿本鐭花浠嬫⒒娴e懙褰掑嫉椤掑倻鐭欓柟杈惧瘜閺佸倿鏌ㄩ悤鍌涘 闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁惧墽鎳撻—鍐偓锝庝簼閹癸綁鏌i鐐搭棞闁靛棙甯掗~婵嬫晲閸涱剙顥氬┑掳鍊楁慨鐑藉磻閻愮儤鍋嬮柣妯荤湽閳ь兛绶氬鎾閻樻爠鍥ㄧ厱閻忕偛澧介悡顖氼熆鐟欏嫭绀€闁宠鍨块、娆戠磼閹惧墎绐楅梻浣告啞椤棝宕橀敐鍡欌偓娲倵楠炲灝鍔氭繛鑼█瀹曟垿骞橀懜闈涙瀭闂佸憡娲﹂崜娑㈡晬濞戙垺鈷戦柛娑樷看濞堟洖鈹戦悙璇ц含闁诡喕鍗抽、姘跺焵椤掆偓閻g兘宕奸弴銊︽櫌婵犮垼娉涢鍡椻枍鐏炶В鏀介柣妯虹仛閺嗏晛鈹戦鑺ュ唉妤犵偛锕ュ鍕箛椤掑偊绱遍梻浣筋潐瀹曟﹢顢氳閺屻劑濡堕崱鏇犵畾闂侀潧鐗嗙€氼垶宕楀畝鍕厱婵炲棗绻戦ˉ銏℃叏婵犲懏顏犵紒杈ㄥ笒铻i柤濮愬€曞鎶芥⒒娴e憡璐¢柍宄扮墦瀹曟垿宕熼娑樹槐濡炪倖鎸堕崹娲煕閹烘嚚褰掓晲閸噥浠╅柣銏╁灡閻╊垶寮诲☉銏犵睄闁逞屽墮鐓ら柣鏃傚帶閺嬩線鏌涢幇闈涙珮闁轰礁鍊块弻娑㈩敃閿濆洨鐣鹃梺纭呭Г濞茬喎顫忓ú顏咁棃婵炴番鍎遍悧鎾愁嚕閹绘巻鍫柛顐g箘閿涙盯姊虹化鏇炲⒉缂佸甯¢幃锟犲即閵忊€斥偓鍫曟煟閹邦厼绲婚柍閿嬫閺屽秹鎸婃径妯恍ч梺闈涙搐鐎氼垳绮诲☉銏犖ㄩ柨鏇楀亾妞ゅ骏鎷�闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁惧墽鎳撻—鍐偓锝庝簻椤掋垺銇勯幇顖毿撻柟渚垮妼椤粓宕卞Δ鈧獮濠勭磽閸屾艾鈧懓顫濋妸鈺佺疅缂佸顑欓崥瀣煕椤愵偅绶氱紓鍐╂礋濮婅櫣鎷犻弻銉偓妤呮煕濡崵鐭掔€规洘鍨块獮妯肩磼濡厧骞堥梻浣告惈濞层垽宕濈仦鍓ь洸闁绘劗鍎ら悡銉︾箾閹寸偟鎳呮繛鎻掔摠閹便劍绻濋崘鈹夸虎闂佽鍠氶崗妯侯嚕閼稿灚鍎熼柟鐐綑閻﹁京绱撻崒姘偓椋庢閿熺姴闂い鏇楀亾鐎规洖缍婂畷濂稿即閻愮數鏆梻浣芥硶閸犳挻鎱ㄩ幘顔肩闁规儼濮ら悡蹇涚叓閸ャ儱鍔ょ痪鎯ф健閺屾稑螣閸忓吋姣堝┑顔硷功缁垳绮悢鐓庣倞鐟滃秵瀵兼惔锝囩=濞达絽鎼牎闂佹悶鍔屽ḿ锟犲箖娴兼惌鏁婄痪鎷岄哺瀵ゆ椽姊洪柅鐐茶嫰婢у鈧鍠栭…鐑藉极閹邦厼绶炴俊顖滅帛濞呭秹姊绘担铏瑰笡闁搞劑娼х叅闁靛牆妫欓崣蹇旂箾閹存瑥鐏柍閿嬪灴濮婃椽顢曢妶鍛捕闂佸吋妞块崹閬嶅疾閸洦鏁婇柛鎾楀拑绱抽柣搴$畭閸庨亶骞忛幋婵愬晠闁靛鍎抽弳鍡涙煥濠靛棙顥滄い鏇熺矌缁辨帞绱掑Ο鑲╃暤濡炪値鍋呯换鍫ャ€佸Δ鍛<闁靛牆鎳忛弳鈺呮⒒閸屾艾鈧嘲霉閸パ€鏋栭柡鍥ュ灩闂傤垶鏌ㄩ弴鐐测偓鍝ョ不椤栫偞鐓ラ柣鏇炲€圭€氾拷3闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁惧墽鎳撻—鍐偓锝庝簼閹癸綁鏌i鐐搭棞闁靛棙甯掗~婵嬫晲閸涱剙顥氬┑掳鍊楁慨鐑藉磻閻愮儤鍋嬮柣妯荤湽閳ь兛绶氬鎾閳╁啯鐝曢梻浣藉Г閿氭い锔诲枤缁辨棃寮撮姀鈾€鎷绘繛杈剧秬濞咃絿鏁☉銏$厱闁哄啠鍋撴繛鑼枛閻涱噣寮介褎鏅濋梺闈涚墕濞诧絿绮径濠庢富闁靛牆妫涙晶閬嶆煕鐎n剙浠遍柟顕嗙節婵$兘鍩¢崒婊冨箺闂備礁鎼ú銊╁磻濞戙垹鐒垫い鎺嗗亾婵犫偓闁秴鐒垫い鎺嶈兌閸熸煡鏌熼崙銈嗗27闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁惧墽鎳撻—鍐偓锝庝簼閹癸綁鏌i鐐搭棞闁靛棙甯掗~婵嬫晲閸涱剙顥氬┑掳鍊楁慨鐑藉磻閻愮儤鍋嬮柣妯荤湽閳ь兛绶氬鎾閳╁啯鐝栭梻渚€鈧偛鑻晶鎵磼椤曞棛鍒伴摶鏍归敐鍫燁仩妞ゆ梹娲熷娲偡閹殿喗鎲奸梺鑽ゅ枂閸庣敻骞冨鈧崺锟犲礃椤忓棴绱查梻浣虹帛閻熴垽宕戦幘缁樼厱闁靛ǹ鍎抽崺锝団偓娈垮枛椤攱淇婇幖浣哥厸闁稿本鐭花浠嬫⒒娴e懙褰掑嫉椤掑倻鐭欓柟杈惧瘜閺佸倿鏌ㄩ悤鍌涘
您现在的位置:佛教导航>> 五明研究>> 英文佛教>>正文内容

Japanese rationalism, Maadhyamika, and some uses of formalism

       

发布时间:2009年04月18日
来源:不详   作者:Douglas Dunsmore Daye
人关注  打印  转发  投稿


·期刊原文


Japanese rationalism, Maadhyamika, and some uses of formalism

By Douglas Dunsmore Daye

Philosophy East & West

V. 24 (1974) pp. 363-368

Copyright 1974 by University of Hawaii Press

Hawaii, USA


p. 363

There are three main aspects of Sueki's paper on which I wish to comment. The first aspect is the relationships between the concepts of rationalism, ideal language expressions (formalism), and Sueki's interpretation of Japanese rationalism. The second aspect is Sueki's interpretation and use of concepts indirectly taken from the Buddhist Maadhyamika school such as "emptiness" (`suunyataa), substancelessness (svabhaava), and "mutual dependence" (pratiitya-samutpaada hereafter, p.s.). The third aspect is his use of ideal language expressions and the justification of formalism in this context. Time permitting, other topics might well have been chosen, for example, duality and relativity, the concept of "nature," and the Buddhist versus Confucian influence.

Sueki begins his article by saying that "Japan has never had any logic and that her philosophy has always been irrational ... and although she once imported Indian formal logic ... it remained undeveloped. Nonetheless it is still wrong to hold that all of Japanese philosophy is irrational." [1] He then offers us an exposition of the thought of the influential Japanese economist Sontoku Ninomiya, which constitutes a counterexample to the above thesis. The following three questions may be asked; Does Japanese thought exhibit a lack of rationality and thereby necessitate this somewhat defensive counterexample? Second, is the absence of a tradition of formal logic a sufficient condition for concluding that a given historical tradition is irrational? Third, does a set of formalized expressions, correctly translated from the ordinary language exposition of a historical tradition, constitute either a sufficient or necessary condition for concluding that a given historical tradition is rational? Here we see the need for some definition of "rationality," which Sueki nowhere gives us.

I am not a specialist in Japanese thought; however, viewing the intricate and subtle development of ideas native to Japan and those imported from both China and India, it is inconceivable to me that the whole complex of Japanese intellectual history (or philosophy) could be considered "irrational."

First, Mr. Sueki does not state, but seems to presuppose, that a consistent act of related ideas is a necessary condition for rationality. This is certainly a reasonable assumption. Second, he also appears to presuppose that the ability to translate these ideas into ideal language formulae constitutes the sole sufficient condition for attributing the term "rational" to a given historical tradition. This I question and do deny.

Regarding the second question, it seems self-evident that the absence of a tradition of formal logic is likewise neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition for concluding that a given tradition is irrational. As a counterexample, witness Confucius, Han Fei Tzu, and Mao Tse-Tung. [2]

The third question, however, brings us to the more complex question of the relationship between formal, ideal-language expressions and concepts embedded in the medium of various natural languages. Let me state my opinion

p. 364

at the outset that the majority of logicians would not wish to presuppose that the methods by which individuals (and ethnic cultural traditions) habitually draw conclusions can be consistently and completely expressed by any combination of the ideal language systems existent today. In other words, I presuppose that all ideal language systems of expressions, within which it is so elegantly clear the degree to which the evidence supports the conclusion, remain the ideal, not the reality, to which rationality must aspire in the mundane world. Logicians and epistemologists would not hold, I believe, that the expression of a set of related concepts in a formalized language is the sole sufficient condition for pronouncing a tradition "rational." Stated quite simply, I think Sueki is flogging a dead, but "rational" horse. [3]

I now wish to compare the Buddhist metaphysical and ontological presuppositions as utilized by Ninomiya and Sueki with their Indian background. Sueki considers four interrelated concepts, namely, substancelessness, emptiness, mutual dependence, and relativity-duality. In comparing their uses of these terms, I shall attempt to differentiate levels or orders of abstraction uncautiously collapsed by Sueki. In particular, I shall focus on the derivation of the ethical obligation of "mutual aid of thanks" from the ontological concept of dependent coorigination (p.s.).

Perhaps the basic metaphysical presupposition Sueki deals with is that of mutually dependent causality. I take it here that he refers to the Buddhist concept of dependent coorigination (p.s.). Since he states that emptiness and mutually dependent origination are interrelated, I also take it that his particular interpretation of p.s. was correctly derived from the Maadhyamika Kaarikaas (ca. 250 A.D. = MK). Naagaarjuna's interpretation of the metaphysical pre-suppositions about substance and interdependent causation (p.s.) emerges in the MK in such statements as "no existents (bhaava) ever occur anywhere which have arisen from themselves, from others, from both, or without a cause." [4] The general interpretation seems to be that the specific individual characteristics of any entity is dependent upon the totality of causes and conditions (hetu and pratyaya) present at any given moment (k.sana) of "its" perception. Sueki's concept of "substancelessness" seems to refer to the Maadhyamika denial of the concept of own-being (svabhaava, of the Lokaayatas and Saa^mkhya dar`sanas). It is important to note that in the MK the concept of own-being (svabhaava) is contrasted with an ordinary language concept of substance. By definition, own-being is a second-order metaphysical postulate which is not subject to causation; it exists through its own agency rather than being caused from the agency of another. By denying own-being, the Buddhists suggest that there is no possibility of a metaphysical/ontological absolute, knowable by conventional means (samv.rtisatya), which is independent of phenomenal causation. That is, phenomena are empty (`suunya) of noncausal ontological absolutes.

p. 365

Sueki notes that the "emptiness of all phenomena in the world..." may lead to spiritual awaking and to the justification of obligations between peoples. [5] These are based on the related concepts of substancelessness and the mutual dependence of all things.

However, it is a mistake to assume that the Maadhyamika polemics concerning substance, causation (mutual and dependent coorigination, pa.ticca-samuppaada) and emptiness refer directly to "things" of the conventionally described world. In fact the MK are really a third-order critique, in that they are criticizing their opponents' views and other Buddhist views, of the ontological and epistemic components of everyday "things." There are at least three orders of description operative in the MK. First is the ordinary language level of "things" in the world, for example, trees, stones, and properties of relationships such as anger and love. Second, there are rival metaphysical and epistemological theories which utilize the terms dharma (an element in a phenomenological analysis of first-person epistemic relations, that is, dharma-vicaya) and svabhaava (own-being). Third, there is the third-order capstone reflexive concept of emptiness (`suunyataa). The early Buddhists (Sthaviravaadins and Sarvaastivaadins) held that the third-person epistemological situations commonly misdescribed in "ordinary language" (first-order language) are better described by reference to second-order relationships rather than to their opponents' metaphysical postulates and ordinary language categories. This "better" second-order description, of reality is composed of a finite set of mutually exclusive, totally exhaustive, ontological components of description, that is, dharmas. By postulating these evaluative and ontological categories these pre-Maadhyamika Buddhists offered an alternate descriptive world-view from a first-person epistemological point of view which contrasts with "ordinary" (third person) descriptive language. The Maadhyamikas strove to refute both these second-order dharma-analysis concepts and the rival second-order concepts of own-being (svabhaava) held by members of opposing schools. Therefore to assume, as does Sueki, a similarity between the ordinary language uses of the word "substance" and the second-order concepts of dharmas and own-beings is simply to collapse levels and to make a category mistake. The values and ontologies associated with each are of different descriptive orders of abstraction.

We now turn to a related Maadhyamika third-order concept, that of "emptiness" (`suunyataa). It is said about emptiness that "emptiness too is empty." [6] The third-order concept of emptiness is derivative and dependent upon the two concepts of mutual (casual) dependence and substancelessness. However, in the MK, emptiness (`suunyataa) is said to be a reflexive designation; [7] it is a descriptive device which has no ontological import. In fact, to reify emptiness is again to make a category mistake. [8] `Suunyataa is a third-order context-restricted term. To suggest an analogy, like the zero, alone, emptiness designates

p. 366

nothing; in a context (for example, 100 apples) it describes a relationship which in combination with other descriptions it does indirectly refer to the world. However, `suunyataa, like the zero, is a meaningful component of a descriptive system which operates at a level of abstraction at some distance from the conventionally (first order) described world of trees and stones. To oversimplify, with respect to orders of abstraction, emptiness (`suunyataa) is somewhat like the difference between a particular sound and the musical transformation rule that the sound of G flat is identical with F sharp in the well-tempered diatonic scale. Ultimately they may "refer" to the "same thing," but to describe one is not to describe the other. The former is a sound; the latter is a rule about the identification of a "sound." So is it with substancelessness (svabhaava) and emptiness; the former is a second-order description. The latter belongs to the third-order description of the ways in which first- and second-order concepts are evaluated and descriptively manipulated. That "emptiness is empty" means that the term `suunyataa has a restricted epistemic role but not an ontological descriptive role. [9]

Sueki uses the terms emptiness, substancelessness, and mutual dependence (= p.s.) as if they belonged to the same order of description. [10] He states (a) "this mutual aid of thanks" (suijoo) is based on (b) the mutual dependence of all things. Since (c) we are all mutually dependent, we (d) cannot recognize ourselves as human beings if we do not recognize others. [11] Consider that (1) all "things" are not epistemically equal to "all dharmas" (c and b). (2) The nonrecognition of others does not necessitate the nonrecognition of ourselves (or conversely, the recognition of ourselves does not necessitate (entail) the recognition of others. [12] Given (1) it does not seem to follow that mutual dependence (p.s.) entails (a). The mutual dependence of all things (b) does not necessitate (entail) (d) any recognition of anything about any obligations (mutual or otherwise) between non-things, that is, people. The epistemic "is" does not entail a soteriological "ought," unless one presupposes the "derived" obligation. Then, of course, there is no need to try to demonstrate "ought" at all. Simply stated, the description of dharmic epistemic dependence (what is metaphysically/ontologically) does not necessitate the obligation ("ought") of mutual aid between people. They are of different types and orders of justification. Therefore Sueki's use of these three terms is somewhat different than that found in the original texts of the MK.

Sueki notes that "Ninomiya thinks that everything in the world has a realition of duality to something other than itself." [13] Here again, as in the MK, we find the ancient Indian idea that the locus of any term ("A"), about which one can speak meaningfully, possesses a logical complement ("~A") which (it is assumed) possesses the ontological status of "A." That is, the early Indians confused the formal relationships of a term ("a" and its logical complement "non-a") with the ontological and referential relationship of that

p. 367

term. Examples of this are the MK term "anyathaabhaava (alter-being) and pratidvandvin (counter-twin). [14] This concept of duality, although similar to such paired items as husband and wife, can certainly not be held today to be a logical principle around which ontological descriptions need be organized. That is, the principle that "everything in the world must be dual to some other thing in the world" ignores the distinction between what may be formally true for terms (and their complements) and whatever may happen to be the case in the empirical world. [15]

I shall now turn to the portion or Sueki's paper in which he formally expresses the interrelationships of Ninomiya's thought; namely, formula 1-40. To this I ask one simple question: In the somewhat extensive use of this ideal language exposition of his interpretation of Buddhist ideas, can one justify the use of the prepositional calculus by appealing to a net gain in clarity of exposition? That is, is it possible to say that with the use of a formal language that the degree of rationality exhibited in the relationships between these ideas is greater? And secondly, are the empirical, logical, ontological, and metaphysical relationships significantly clearer than could have been achieved without the use of the calculus? I think not. Surely what is in question here is the extent to which ideal-language analysis, with its necessary and legitimate restrictions of the multiple semantic values of natural language terms, does generate sufficiently and legitimately accurate expressions which describes both what is required for formal argumentation and what is presupposed evaluatively and ontologically in the multiple historical uses of natural language terms.

I am also aware that the use of formal expressions does add an aura of precision and modernity to the exposition of any set of ideas which can be so expressed. If there is disagreement about the truth value of the premises, as noted in my discussion of levels of abstraction and description in the MK, then, a fortiori, the remaining question of the utility of formal expression of these premises becomes a somewhat subordinate question. However, in the context of this conference it is important. On this point I must regretfully conclude and simply state that I find no significant degree of clarity of exposition gained by the uses of the formal expressions. I am in complete agreement with Sueki (part V, line 1) that Ninomiya may be easily recognized as a very rational thinker; but he can be so recognized without the use of this formalism.

In summary I wish to state four points. First, Sueki has given us an excellent and informative paper about the uses of imported Chinese and Indian Buddhist ideas as assimilated and developed by a relatively modern Japanese thinker. He has shown us how these ideas have been modified to accommodate the impact of modern ideas on nineteenth-century Japan. Second, his thesis that Japanese thought is indeed rational, to my mind, has never been in doubt,

p. 368

in spite of Nakamura's remarks. Thirdly, it is important (if somewhat pedantic) to point out the differences in interpretation between the related concepts found in the MK and their subsequent interpretation of nineteenth-century Japanese thought. Fourth, Sueki's use of a formal calculus seems to communicate little additional clarity which, to my mind, could not have been communicated, in a quite rational manner, without the use of formalism. However, this is not to say that I have not enjoyed and profited by reading Sueki's article; on the contrary, I have found it extremely interesting to see new uses of old ideas in a modern East-West context. It is only to say that if one does not assume that the formulation of proportions from natural languages into a formal system is a sufficient condition for rationality, then such interesting concepts, important to all interested in East-West philosophy, can be understood quite rationally without resorting to formalism.

NOTES

1. A footnote documenting these opinions would have been extremely fruitful.

2. Although there is yin-ming which is Buddhist Chinese, there is almost no development of a meta-yin-ming, likewise for the latter Mohists.

3. Perhaps Sueki has in mind criticisms of Japanese culture such as those found in, for example, Hajime Nakamura's book, The Way of Thinking of Eastern Peoples (Honolulu: East-West Center Press, 1968, for example, chapt. 36 "Non-rationalistic Tendencies," pp. 531-576) Without more documentation and discussion these interesting matters lay outside the dimensions of the remainder of Sueki's article. A cultural dimension to the discussion is obviously missing.

4. 1.3, Prasannapadaa, p. 12, v. 1.

5. P. 6, v. i.

6. (MK 13:7-7).

7. Praj~napti, MK 24:18.

8. MK 13-: 7-8.

9. One might use, for example, predicates of predicates to express third-order terms, but I see no great degree of clarity achieved by the use of such mechanisms also available in descriptions within natural language.

10. For example, F36, p. 14.

11. P. 5-6, ii, underlining and identification letters are mine.

12. (s) (o) (~ (Rs Ro))
Where: R DF recognition (a property)
S DF ourselves
O DF others.

13. F 16, p. 10.

14. "When there is no own being, whence might other beings be? For the own being of other-being is called other beings." 15.3, cf. 22.29.

15. A`soka Gangadean of Haverford College noted a crucial point (in subsequent conversation). Sueki's concept of "duality" blurs the distinction between logical contraries and complements. The former are limited to types by general semantical rules; the latter are not limited in such a manner. Although "true-false, clean and unclean" are clearly limited to certain types, Sueki's "husband-wife duality" is not clearly limited in the same way. It is this latter use of "duality" that provides the basis for his "duality" of body and mind.

没有相关内容

欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn


            在线投稿

------------------------------ 权 益 申 明 -----------------------------
1.所有在佛教导航转载的第三方来源稿件,均符合国家相关法律/政策、各级佛教主管部门规定以及和谐社会公序良俗,除了注明其来源和原始作者外,佛教导航会高度重视和尊重其原始来源的知识产权和著作权诉求。但是,佛教导航不对其关键事实的真实性负责,读者如有疑问请自行核实。另外,佛教导航对其观点的正确性持有审慎和保留态度,同时欢迎读者对第三方来源稿件的观点正确性提出批评;
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。