2025濠电姷鏁告慨鐑藉极閸涘﹥鍙忛柣鎴f閺嬩線鏌涘☉姗堟敾闁告瑥绻橀弻鐔虹磼閵忕姵鐏嶉梺绋块椤︻垶鈥﹂崸妤佸殝闂傚牊绋戦~宀€绱撴担鍝勭彙闁搞儜鍜佸晣闂佽瀛╃粙鎺曟懌闁诲繐娴氶崢濂告箒濠电姴锕ら幊搴㈢閹灔搴ㄥ炊瑜濋煬顒€鈹戦垾宕囧煟鐎规洜鍠栭、姗€鎮欏顔锯偓鎾⒒閸屾瑧顦﹂柟璇х節閹兘濡疯瀹曞弶鎱ㄥ璇蹭壕閻庢鍠栭…鐑藉极閹邦厼绶炲┑鐘插閸氬懘姊绘担鐟邦嚋缂佽鍊歌灋妞ゆ挾鍊e☉銏犵妞ゆ挾濮烽敍婊堟⒑缂佹ê濮﹂柛鎾寸懇瀹曟繈濡堕崱娆戭啎缂佺虎鍙冮ˉ鎾跺姬閳ь剟鎮楀▓鍨灈妞ゎ厾鍏橀獮鍐閵堝懎绐涙繝鐢靛Т鐎氼喛鍊撮梻鍌氬€风粈渚€骞夐敓鐘茬闁糕剝绋戝婵囥亜閺冨倻鎽傞柛鐔锋噽缁辨捇宕掑顑藉亾閹间礁纾归柣鎴eГ閸ゅ嫰鏌ら幖浣规锭闁搞劍姊归妵鍕箻閸楃偟浠奸梺鎼炲妼閸婂潡寮诲☉銏╂晝闁挎繂妫涢ˇ銉╂⒑閽樺鏆熼柛鐘崇墵瀵寮撮悢铏诡啎闂佺粯鍔﹂崜姘舵偟閺囥垺鈷戠紒瀣儥閸庡繑淇婇锝囩疄鐎殿喛顕ч埥澶婎潩椤愶絽濯伴梻浣告啞閹稿棝鍩€椤掆偓鍗遍柛顐g箥濞撳鏌曢崼婵囧殗闁绘稒绮撻弻鐔煎礄閵堝棗顏�4闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄥジ鏌熼惂鍝ョМ闁哄矉缍侀、姗€鎮欓幖顓燁棧闂備線娼уΛ娆戞暜閹烘缍栨繝闈涱儐閺呮煡鏌涘☉鍗炲妞ゃ儲鑹鹃埞鎴炲箠闁稿﹥顨嗛幈銊╂倻閽樺锛涢梺缁樺姉閸庛倝宕戠€n喗鐓熸俊顖濆吹濠€浠嬫煃瑜滈崗娑氭濮橆剦鍤曢柟缁㈠枛椤懘鏌嶉埡浣告殲闁绘繃娲熷缁樻媴閽樺-鎾绘煥濮橆厹浜滈柨鏃囶嚙閺嬨倗绱掓潏銊︻棃鐎殿喗鎸虫慨鈧柍閿亾闁归绮换娑欐綇閸撗呅氬┑鐐叉嫅缁插潡寮灏栨闁靛骏绱曢崢閬嶆⒑閸濆嫬鏆婇柛瀣尰缁绘盯鎳犻鈧弸娑㈡煟濞戝崬娅嶇€殿喕绮欓、妯款槼闁哄懏绻堝娲濞戞艾顣哄┑鐐额嚋缁茶法鍒掗鐔风窞濠电姴瀛╃€靛矂姊洪棃娑氬婵☆偅绋掗弲鍫曟焼瀹ュ棛鍘遍柣搴秵閸撴瑦绂掗柆宥嗙厵妞ゆ洖妫涚弧鈧繝纰夌磿閸忔﹢宕洪敓鐘茬<婵犲﹤鍟粻娲⒒閸屾瑧顦﹂柟纰卞亜鐓ら柕濞炬櫅绾剧粯绻涢幋娆忕仼闁绘帒鐏氶妵鍕箳閸℃ぞ澹曟繝鐢靛Л閸嬫捇姊洪鈧粔鎾倿閸偁浜滈柟鍝勭Х閸忓矂鏌涢悢鍝ュ弨闁哄瞼鍠栧畷娆撳Χ閸℃浼�26闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄥジ鏌熼惂鍝ョМ闁哄矉缍侀、姗€鎮欓幖顓燁棧闂備線娼уΛ娆戞暜閹烘缍栨繝闈涱儐閺呮煡鏌涘☉鍗炲妞ゃ儲鑹鹃埞鎴炲箠闁稿﹥顨嗛幈銊╂倻閽樺锛涢梺缁樺姉閸庛倝宕戠€n喗鐓熸俊顖濆吹濠€浠嬫煃瑜滈崗娑氭濮橆剦鍤曢柟缁㈠枛椤懘鏌嶉埡浣告殲闁绘繃鐗犲缁樼瑹閳ь剟鍩€椤掑倸浠滈柤娲诲灡閺呭爼骞嶉鍓э紲濡炪倖娲栧Λ娑㈠礆娴煎瓨鎳氶柡宥庣亹瑜版帗鏅查柛顐ゅ櫏娴犫晛顪冮妶鍡樷拹婵炶尙鍠庨~蹇撁洪鍛画闂佽顔栭崰妤呭箟婵傚憡鈷戦柤濮愬€曢弸鍌炴煕鎼达絾鏆鐐插暙椤粓鍩€椤掑嫬鏄ラ柨鐔哄Т缁€鍐┿亜韫囨挻锛旂紒杈ㄧ叀濮婄粯鎷呴搹鐟扮闂佽崵鍠嗛崹钘夌暦閹达箑绠荤紓浣贯缚閸橀亶姊洪棃娴ㄥ綊宕曢幎钘夋槬闁挎繂娲犻崑鎾斥枔閸喗鐏堝銈庡弮閺€杈ㄧ┍婵犲洤绠瑰ù锝呮憸閸樻悂姊虹粙鎸庢拱闁活収鍠氶懞杈ㄧ鐎n偀鎷绘繛杈剧到閹虫瑨銇愰幒鎴濈彉濡炪倖甯掗崐濠氭儗濞嗘挻鐓欓弶鍫熷劤閻︽粓鏌℃担绋库偓鍧楀蓟閵娾晜鍋嗛柛灞剧☉椤忥拷 闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄥジ鏌熼惂鍝ョМ闁哄矉缍侀、姗€鎮欓幖顓燁棧闂備線娼уΛ娆戞暜閹烘缍栨繝闈涱儐閺呮煡鏌涘☉鍗炲妞ゃ儲鑹鹃埞鎴炲箠闁稿﹥顨嗛幈銊╂倻閽樺锛涢梺缁樺姉閸庛倝宕戠€n喗鐓熸俊顖濆吹濠€浠嬫煃瑜滈崗娑氭濮橆剦鍤曢柟缁㈠枛椤懘鏌eΟ鑽ゅ灩闁搞儯鍔庨崢閬嶆煟韫囨洖浠滃褌绮欓幃锟狀敍濮樿偐鍞甸柣鐔哥懃鐎氼厾绮堥埀顒勬⒑鐎圭媭娼愰柛銊ユ健閵嗕礁鈻庨幋鐘碉紲闂佽鍎虫晶搴g玻濡ゅ懏鈷掑ù锝呮啞閸熺偞銇勯鐐搭棦鐎规洘锕㈤弫鎰板幢濞嗗苯浜炬繛宸簼閸婂灚顨ラ悙鑼虎闁告梹纰嶇换娑㈡嚑椤掆偓閳诲牏鈧娲橀崹鍧楃嵁濮椻偓閹虫粓妫冨☉娆戔偓顓㈡⒒娴e憡鍟炴繛璇х畵瀹曟粌鈽夐姀鈩冩珫濠电偞鍨崹娲煕閹达附鐓曟繛鎴炃氶惇瀣箾閸喐绀€闁宠鍨块幃娆戞嫚瑜戦崥顐︽⒑鐠団€虫灆闁告濞婇妴浣割潩鐠鸿櫣鍔﹀銈嗗坊閸嬫捇鏌i敐鍥у幋鐎规洖銈稿鎾Ω閿旇姤鐝滄繝鐢靛О閸ㄧ厧鈻斿☉銏╂晞闁糕剝銇涢弸宥夋倶閻愮紟鎺楀绩娴犲鐓熸俊顖濇娴犳盯鏌¢崱蹇旀珔闁宠鍨块、娆撴嚍閵夈儱鏀俊銈囧Х閸嬫盯鏁冮妷銉殫闁告洦鍨扮粻娑欍亜閹烘垵浜扮紒閬嶄憾濮婄粯鎷呯粵瀣秷閻庤娲橀敃銏ゃ€佸鎰佹▌闂佸搫琚崝鎴炰繆閸洖骞㈤柡鍥╁Х閻i箖姊绘笟鈧ḿ褔鎮ч崱娆屽亾濮樼厧鐏︾€规洘顨呴悾婵嬪礋椤掑倸骞堟繝鐢靛仜濡鎹㈤幋位澶愬閳╁啫寮挎繝鐢靛Т閹冲繘顢旈悩鐢电<閺夊牄鍔岀粭鎺楁懚閿濆鐓犲┑顔藉姇閳ь剚娲栭锝夊箮閼恒儮鎷绘繛杈剧到閹诧紕鎷归敓鐘崇厓鐎瑰嫭澹嗘晶锔锯偓瑙勬礃閸ㄥ灝鐣烽悢纰辨晬婵炴垶眉濡叉劖淇婇悙顏勨偓鏍箰閻愵剚鍙忓瀣椤ユ艾霉閻樺樊鍎愰柣鎾存礋閹﹢鎮欓幓鎺嗘寖闂佺懓鍟垮Λ娆撳Φ閸曨垰妫樻繛鍡欏亾閳诲牓姊洪崫鍕拱缂佸鎹囬崺鈧い鎺戯功缁夌敻鏌涚€n亝鍣归柣锝呭槻閻f繈宕熼鍌氬箰闂佽绻掗崑娑欐櫠娴犲鐓″鑸靛姈閻撶喖鏌ㄥ┑鍡橆棤缂佺姷鍋ら弻娑㈠煘閹傚濠碉紕鍋戦崐鏍暜閹烘柡鍋撳鐓庡濠㈣娲樼换婵嗩潩椤撶姴骞楅梻浣哥秺閸嬪﹪宕伴弽顓炵閻庯綆鍠楅悡鏇㈡倵閿濆簼绨婚柍褜鍓欏ḿ鈥愁嚕婵犳艾鍗抽柣鏃堫棑缁愮偤姊虹化鏇炲⒉閽冮亶鏌e┑鍥ㄧ婵﹨娅g槐鎺懳熺拠鍙夋闂備礁鎽滄慨鐢告偋閻樺樊鍤曞┑鐘崇閺呮悂鏌eΟ鍨毢闁稿﹦鍋ゅ铏光偓鍦У閵嗗啯淇婇悙鏉戠闁告帗甯″畷濂稿即閻斿弶瀚奸梻鍌欑贰閸嬪棝宕戝☉銏″殣妞ゆ牗绋掑▍鐘炽亜閺冨倹娅曠紒鈾€鍋撻梻渚€鈧偛鑻晶鎾煛鐏炶姤顥滄い鎾炽偢瀹曘劑顢涘顑洖鈹戦敍鍕杭闁稿﹥鐗滈弫顔界節閸ャ劌娈戦梺鍓插亝濞叉牠鎮块鈧弻锛勪沪鐠囨彃濮曢梺缁樻尰閻熲晠寮诲☉銏犵婵炲棗绻嗛崑鎾诲冀椤愮喎浜炬慨妯煎亾鐎氾拷闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄧ粯銇勯幒瀣仾闁靛洤瀚伴獮鍥敍濮f寧鎹囬弻鐔哥瑹閸喖顬堝銈庡亝缁挸鐣烽崡鐐嶆棃鍩€椤掑嫮宓佸┑鐘插绾句粙鏌涚仦鎹愬闁逞屽墰閹虫捇锝炲┑瀣╅柍杞拌兌閻ゅ懐绱撴担鍓插剱妞ゆ垶鐟╁畷銉р偓锝庡枟閻撴洘銇勯幇闈涗簼缂佽埖姘ㄧ槐鎾诲礃閳哄倻顦板┑顔硷龚濞咃綁骞忛悩璇茶摕闁靛鍠掗崑鎾澄旈崨顔惧幈濠碘槅鍨靛畷鐢告儗閹烘柡鍋撶憴鍕闁搞劌娼¢悰顔嘉熼懖鈺冿紲濠碘槅鍨抽崢褔鐛崼銉︹拻濞达絽鎲¢幆鍫熺箾鐏炲倸鐏茬€规洘绻勬禒锕傚礈瑜滃ú鎼佹⒑缂佹ê濮夐柛搴涘€濋幃锟犲Ψ閿斿墽顔曢梺鐟邦嚟閸嬬喖骞婇崨顔剧闁圭粯甯為幗鐘绘煙娓氬灝濡界紒缁樼箞瀹曟﹢鍩炴径姝屾闂傚倷娴囬鏍窗濮樿泛绀傛俊顖欒閸ゆ洟鏌ょ粙璺ㄤ粵闁稿海鍠栭弻鐔兼倷椤掍胶绋囬梺浼欑畳娴滎剛妲愰幘璇茬<婵﹩鍏橀崑鎾搭槹鎼淬埄鍋ㄩ梺璺ㄥ枔婵挳姊婚娑栦簻闁哄洦顨呮禍楣冩倵鐟欏嫭绀€缂傚秴锕ら悾閿嬬附缁嬪灝宓嗛梺缁樺姉閺佹悂寮抽锔解拻濞达綀濮ょ涵鍫曟煕閻樿櫕灏伴柟渚垮姂楠炴﹢顢欓懖鈺婃敤闂備浇顫夐崕鍏兼叏閵堝鍋傞煫鍥ㄧ〒閸欐捇鏌涢妷锝呭姎闁告柣鍊楅惀顏堝箚瑜庨崑銉╂煛鐏炲墽鈽夐摶锝夋煕韫囨挸鎮戞慨锝呯墕閳规垿顢欑涵宄板缂備緡鍣崹宕囧垝椤撱垺鍋勯柣鎾虫捣閸婄偤鎮峰⿰鍐i悗闈涘悑閹棃鏁愰崶鈺嬬闯濠电偠鎻徊浠嬪箹椤愶絿澧¢梻鍌欑劍閹爼宕濈仦缁撶細闁跨喓濮寸粻鏍归崗鍏煎剹闁轰礁锕﹂惀顏堝箯瀹€鍕懙閻庣偣鍊栧钘夘潖濞差亝鐒婚柣鎰蔼鐎氭澘顭胯椤曨參鍩€椤掍緡鍟忛柛鐘崇墵閳ワ箓鎮滈挊澶嬬€梺褰掑亰閸樿偐娆㈤悙缈犵箚妞ゆ牗绮庣敮娑欑箾閸涱厾效婵﹦绮幏鍛存惞閻熸壆顐奸梻浣规偠閸旀垵岣胯閸欏懘姊洪棃娑氬婵☆偅鐟╁畷锝堢疀閺冨倻顔曢梺鐟扮摠閻熴儵鎮橀鍫熺厓闂佸灝顑呴悘瀛樻叏婵犲啯銇濇い銏℃礋婵″爼宕ㄩ鍌涘礋闂傚倷绀侀崥瀣渻閸ф鍨傞梺顒€绉撮悿楣冩煕椤愶絾澶勯柡浣革躬閺屾盯骞樺Δ鈧幏鎴犳閹惰姤鐓熼幖杈剧磿閻n參鏌涙惔銊ゆ喚妤犵偛绻橀獮瀣攽閹邦剚娅婇梻渚€娼чˇ顓㈠磿閹惰棄姹查柛鈩冪⊕閻撱儲绻濋棃娑欘棡妞ゃ儲绮嶉妵鍕即閻旇櫣鐓傜紓浣介哺鐢偟妲愰幒鎳崇喖鎳栭埡鍐╂濠碉紕鍋戦崐銈夊磻閸涱垱宕查柛顐犲劘閳ь兛绀佽灃闁告侗鍘鹃敍婊堟⒑闂堟稓澧曢柟鍐茬箻瀵娊鍩¢崨顔规嫽闂佺ǹ鏈懝楣冨焵椤掆偓閸㈡煡婀侀梺鎼炲劀閳ь剟寮搁弽顓熺厸闁搞儯鍎遍悘鈺呮⒒閸屻倕鐏﹂柡灞诲姂瀵挳鎮欏ù瀣壕闁告縿鍎虫稉宥嗐亜閺嶎偄浠﹂柣鎾卞劦閺岋綁寮撮悙娴嬪亾閸︻厸鍋撳鐐3闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄥジ鏌熼惂鍝ョМ闁哄矉缍侀、姗€鎮欓幖顓燁棧闂備線娼уΛ娆戞暜閹烘缍栨繝闈涱儐閺呮煡鏌涘☉鍗炲妞ゃ儲鑹鹃埞鎴炲箠闁稿﹥顨嗛幈銊╂倻閽樺锛涢梺缁樺姉閸庛倝宕戠€n喗鐓熸俊顖濆吹濠€浠嬫煃瑜滈崗娑氭濮橆剦鍤曢柟缁㈠枛椤懘鏌嶉埡浣告殲闁绘繃娲熷缁樻媴閽樺-鎾绘煥濮橆厹浜滈柨鏃囶嚙閺嬨倗绱掓潏銊︻棃鐎殿喗鎸虫慨鈧柍閿亾闁归绮换娑欐綇閸撗呅氬┑鐐叉嫅缁插潡寮灏栨闁靛骏绱曢崢閬嶆⒑閸濆嫬鏆婇柛瀣尰缁绘盯鎳犻鈧弸娑㈡煟濞戝崬娅嶇€殿喕绮欓、妯款槼闁哄懏绻堝娲濞戞艾顣哄┑鐐额嚋缁茶法鍒掗鐔风窞濠电姴瀛╃€靛矂姊洪棃娑氬婵☆偅绋掗弲鍫曟焼瀹ュ棛鍘遍柣搴秵閸撴瑦绂掗柆宥嗙厵妞ゆ洖妫涚弧鈧繝纰夌磿閸忔﹢宕洪敓鐘茬<婵犲﹤鍟粻娲⒒閸屾瑧顦﹂柟纰卞亜鐓ら柕濞炬櫅绾剧粯绻涢幋娆忕仼闁绘帒鐏氶妵鍕箳閸℃ぞ澹曟繝鐢靛Л閸嬫捇姊洪鈧粔鎾倿閸偁浜滈柟鍝勭Х閸忓矂鏌涢悢鍝ュ弨闁哄瞼鍠栧畷娆撳Χ閸℃浼�29闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄥジ鏌熼惂鍝ョМ闁哄矉缍侀、姗€鎮欓幖顓燁棧闂備線娼уΛ娆戞暜閹烘缍栨繝闈涱儐閺呮煡鏌涘☉鍗炲妞ゃ儲鑹鹃埞鎴炲箠闁稿﹥顨嗛幈銊╂倻閽樺锛涢梺缁樺姉閸庛倝宕戠€n喗鐓熸俊顖濆吹濠€浠嬫煃瑜滈崗娑氭濮橆剦鍤曢柟缁㈠枛椤懘鏌嶉埡浣告殲闁绘繃鐗犲缁樼瑹閳ь剟鍩€椤掑倸浠滈柤娲诲灡閺呭爼骞嶉鍓э紲濡炪倖娲栧Λ娑㈠礆娴煎瓨鎳氶柡宥庣亹瑜版帗鏅查柛顐ゅ櫏娴犫晛顪冮妶鍡樷拹婵炶尙鍠庨~蹇撁洪鍛画闂佽顔栭崰妤呭箟婵傚憡鈷戦柤濮愬€曢弸鍌炴煕鎼达絾鏆鐐插暙椤粓鍩€椤掑嫬鏄ラ柨鐔哄Т缁€鍐┿亜韫囨挻锛旂紒杈ㄧ叀濮婄粯鎷呴搹鐟扮闂佽崵鍠嗛崹钘夌暦閹达箑绠荤紓浣贯缚閸橀亶姊洪棃娴ㄥ綊宕曢幎钘夋槬闁挎繂娲犻崑鎾斥枔閸喗鐏堝銈庡弮閺€杈ㄧ┍婵犲洤绠瑰ù锝呮憸閸樻悂姊虹粙鎸庢拱闁活収鍠氶懞杈ㄧ鐎n偀鎷绘繛杈剧到閹虫瑨銇愰幒鎴濈彉濡炪倖甯掗崐濠氭儗濞嗘挻鐓欓弶鍫熷劤閻︽粓鏌℃担绋库偓鍧楀蓟閵娾晜鍋嗛柛灞剧☉椤忥拷
您现在的位置:佛教导航>> 五明研究>> 英文佛教>>正文内容

Euthanasia in Buddhism and Christianity

       

发布时间:2009年04月18日
来源:不详   作者:Damien Keown
人关注  打印  转发  投稿


·期刊原文


Killing, karma and caring: Euthanasia in Buddhism and Christianity

by Damien Keown

Journal of Medical Ethics

Vol. 21 No.5 Oct.1995 Pp.265-269

Copyright by Journal of Medical Ethics



Abstract

In 1993 The Parliament of the World's Religions produced a declaration
known as A Global Ethic which set out fundamental points of agreement
on moral issues between the religions of the world. However, the
declaration did not deal explicitly with medical ethics. This article
examines Buddhist and Christian perspectives on euthanasia and finds
that in spite of theft cultural and theological differences both
oppose it for broadly similar reasons. Both traditions reject
consequentialist patterns of justification and espouse a 'sanctity of
life' position which precludes the intentional destruction of human
life by act or omission.

Introduction

The religions of the world are becoming increasingly aware that what unites
them in ethics is greater than what divides them in theology. An
interesting counterpoint to the disintegration of moral consensus in the
postmodern world can be seen in the impetus towards dialogue and mutual
understanding on the part of traditions which for much of their history
have been antagonistic. As they search their ancient teachings for
solutions to contemporary dilemmas, Christians, Muslims and Jews are
becoming increasingly aware of the common ground they share. The consensus
which is emerging in key areas suggests that scepticism regarding moral
objectivity may be misplaced.

The moral consensus among religions was given expression in a codified form
by the Parliament of the World's Religions which met in Chicago in late
1993. The parliament produced a declaration which reveals an impressive
degree of accord. The declaration states: 'We affirm that a common set of
core values is found in the teachings of the religions, and that these form
the basis of a global ethic' (1). In its affirmation that there is 'an
irrevocable, unconditional norm for all areas of life, for families and
communities, for races, nations and religions' (1) it characterises these
core values as objective and universal moral truths.

Adding further weight to the suggestion that a consensus on ethical
fundamentals exists among the major religious traditions are the views of
the eastern religions, whose voice has been little heard to date. Perhaps
the most influential of these is Buddhism, a religion whose adherents in
Asia number roughly 500 million and which is rapidly making inroads in the
West. Arnold Toynbee has described the encounter between Buddhism and
Christianity as 'one of the greatest collisions of the 21st Century,' (2)
and although it is too soon to predict the outcome of this encounter it is
undeniable that it will be of significance. The purpose of this paper,
however, is not to speculate about the future, and is limited to indicating
the existence of common ground in one specific area of medical ethics,
namely euthanasia. By 'euthanasia' we mean the intentional killing of a
patient by act or omission as part of his or her medical care. We are not
concerned, therefore, with either the administration of palliative drugs,
or the withdrawal of futile or excessively burdensome treatment, which may,
as a foreseen side-effect, hasten death.

Buddhist ethics

Reliable information on Buddhism has been available in the West for less
than a century and a half and the study of Buddhist ethics is a nascent
discipline. The existence of alien traditions such as Buddhism has long
been seen as providing evidence of moral diversity and support for moral
relativism. A closer examination, however, suggests that this view is
mistaken. What is particularly striking in the case of Buddhism (3) is that
despite its different theological premises (most radically its denial of
both a supreme being and the soul), it reaches ethical conclusions which
are very similar to those of the Semitic religions.

In terms of the categories of Western ethics Buddhism could best be summed
up as a teleological virtue ethic. Its nearest analogue would be
Aristotle's eudaimonism as developed in the tradition of natural law (4).
In its teachings on karma Buddhism affirms that every moral act has both
transitive and intransitive effects. The transitive effects are seen in the
impact our moral choices have on others, while the intransitive effects are
the changes in the character of the subject brought about through the
performance of virtuous or wicked deeds. The doctrine of karma also holds
that the circumstances of rebirth are determined by an individual's moral
status at death. This means that the hedonic tone of any given existence is
conditioned by antecedent moral deeds. While moral actions produce pleasant
and unpleasant consequences in the form of transitive and intransitive
effects, however, the moral status of an act is not determined by its
consequences. For Buddhism this is determined instead by the conformity
between what is intended and the eternal moral law (Dharma), the
requirements of which can be known through scripture and reason (5).

The sanctity of life

Buddhism's approach to medical ethics is informed by its belief in the
sanctity of life. This pan-Indian belief finds ethical expression among the
major religious traditions in the form of the principle of non-harming
(ahimsa). In the case of Buddhism, which is atheistic, respect for life is
grounded not in its divine origin but in its spiritual destiny, namely the
state of final perfection known as nirvana. From this affirmative valuation
of life flow precepts forbidding its intentional destruction (6).

Despite its highly sophisticated psychology Buddhism makes no attempt to
distinguish certain faculties as indicators of moral personhood. Existence
is a continuum of changing states: all states are impermanent, and the
possession or absence of certain faculties or qualities in the course of a
determined psycho-physical existence is of no moral significance.
Individual life in any one existence begins at conception and ends at
death: in the interval between the subject is entitled to full moral
respect regardless of the stage of psycho-physical development attained or
the mental capacities enjoyed (7).

Euthanasia

No euphemism such as 'euthanasia' is found in early Buddhist canonical
sources, nor is the morality of the practice discussed specifically in the
discourses (sutta) of the Buddha (8). As an act or omission involving the
intentional destruction of life, however, it would undoubtedly be
prohibited by Buddhist precepts. Confirmation of this can be found in the
Monastic Rule (Vinaya), a corpus of canonical literature which sets out the
regulations governing monastic life. The Monastic Rule is an authoritative
source for Buddhist ethics, and includes a body of case law in which the
Buddha is represented as giving judgment on specific matters. The cases
relevant to euthanasia are recounted under the rubric of the precept
against the destruction of human life (the third parajika). The penalty for
breaking the precept is the severest which can be imposed: lifelong
excommunication.

The circumstances leading to the promulgation of this precept have a direct
bearing on euthanasia. The Buddha included it in the monastic code on
discovering that a number of monks had either killed themselves or asked
others to kill them after developing disgust for their bodies, an attitude
not unknown in ascetic traditions. Some monks committed suicide, some
killed one another, and others invoked the aid of an assistant from outside
the order who killed them with a knife. When the Buddha found out he
immediately took action to prevent any recurrence by introducing a precept
forbidding the destruction of human life. The precept expressly forbids
both killing a human being and seeking assistance in dying (literally
'looking for a knife-wielder') (9).

The promulgation of the precept in these circumstances suggests that
voluntary euthanasia (that is, euthanasia at the individual's request) is
immoral from a Buddhist perspective. The fact that the monks were
autonomous agents seems to have had no beating on the matter, which implies
that the principle of the sanctity of life cannot be overridden by an
appeal to autonomy. It is arguable that the prohibition was introduced
because the monks who sought euthanasia in the case in point had done so
under the influence of religious zeal and without due time for sober
reflection. This argument is, however, unpersuasive, since the precept
imposes an unqualified prohibition. Such a prohibition is, moreover, quite
consistent with the corpus of early Buddhist ethical teachings which do not
contemplate any circumstances in which the destruction of life might be
condoned (10). In addition there are further cases in the Monastic Rule
itself where the immorality of euthanasia clearly does not turn on the
absence of due consideration. Certain of these cases involve 'quality of
life' issues: one concerns terminal care (11), and two the long-term care
of patients with serious disabilities (amputated limbs) (12).

The most interesting of these cases is the first, the one involving
terminal care. The motive is stated to have been compassion for the
suffering of a dying monk. According to the influential fifth-century
commentator Buddhaghosa, those found guilty in this case took no direct
action to terminate life but merely suggested to a dying monk that death
would be preferable to his present condition. Despite this apparently
benevolent motive, namely to spare a dying person unnecessary pain, the
judgment handed down was that those involved were guilty of a breach of the
precept. What had they done wrong? In Buddhaghosa's view the essence of
their wrongdoing was that the guilty monks made death their aim
(Va.ii.464). It would therefore appear immoral from a Buddhist perspective
to embark on any course of action whose aim is the destruction of human
life, regardless of the agent's motive (13).

The circumstances in which the precept was promulgated and the cases
referred to above are directly relevant to the two main grounds on which
euthanasia is thought by some to be justifiable, namely beneficence, either
in alleviating pain or terminating life which is no longer thought to be a
benefit, or respect for autonomy. The canonical evidence suggests that
neither of these grounds provides justification for euthanasia from a
Buddhist perspective.

The above does not, however, commit Buddhism to the view that life must be
preserved at all costs. Buddhism is only too aware of the fragile and
transitory nature of life, but as individual life is a continuum which
constantly re-manifests itself Buddhism does not seek to prolong it by
artificial means simply because it is technologically possible. There is
accordingly no requirement to carry out futile or unduly burdensome
treatments, such as resuscitating the dying. The intentional hastening of
death is, however, morally unacceptable in all circumstances.

Christian ethics

Given the number of Christian denominations, and their more or less varying
traditions, it is hardly surprising that not all Christians agree on all
ethical issues. The major Christian tradition, Catholicism, subscribes to
an ethics based on natural law, whereas the Lutheran churches do not.
Nevertheless, both traditions would join in rejecting a consequentialist
ethic, one which holds that the morality of an action turns solely on its
consequences, an ethic advanced by a number of prominent contemporary
bioethicists.

The Christian tradition rejects such bioethicists in favour of St Paul, who
taught that certain conduct is intrinsically wrong and should be avoided
regardless of any good consequences that might flow from it. In short, a
good end does not justify a bad means: evil may not be done that good may
come of it (14). Christian ethics holds that, while consequences may well
be relevant in assessing the morality of an act or omission, the morality
of an act or omission is not determined by its consequences. So whereas the
Christian rules out, say, torturing children as intrinsically wrong, the
consequentialist does not. This is not the place to critique
consequentialism; its incoherency has been exposed elsewhere (15). Our
purpose here is simply to note the consensus among Christians and Buddhists
in rejecting the consequentialist ethical approach which typically
underlies the case for the legalisation of euthanasia.

The sanctity of life

Few ethical concepts are more widely misunderstood or persistently
misrepresented than that of the 'sanctity of life'. As developed and
understood in Christian thought, it holds that as life is a gift from God
it is to be cherished. As explained by the Anglican and Catholic bishops in
their joint submission to the House of Lords Select Committee on Medical
Ethics (a submission which states that it would also enjoy the support of
the Free Churches): 'All human beings are to be valued, irrespective of
age, sex, race, religion, social status or their potential for achievement'
(16) and 'the deliberate taking of human life is prohibited except in
self-defence or the legitimate defence of others' (17). In this
understanding, which roots the fundamental value of each human being in his
or her creation by God and in the image of God (but which can also be
articulated in purely secular terms) human life is a basic good as opposed
to an instrumental good: a good in itself rather than as a means to an end,
whether that end be conceived of as life of a certain minimum 'quality', or
the good of the state, or anything else.

Life is not, however, considered to be an absolute value, in the sense that
it must be preserved at all costs. As the bishops make clear: 'Neither of
our Churches insists that a dying or seriously ill person should be kept
alive by all possible means for as long as possible' (18). They add that it
can be perfectly proper to administer palliative care even if it
incidentally shortens life. Adverting to the doctrine of 'double effect',
they note that 'There is a proper and fundamental ethical distinction. . .
between that which is intended and that which is foreseen but unintended'
(19).

Euthanasia

The principles sketched above explain the basis of the Christian opposition
to euthanasia. As the wrongness of intentional killing obtains regardless
of the consequences, that opposition applies whatever the condition of the
patient. As the joint submission states, the vulnerable deserve not less
protection, but 'special care and protection' (20). Adherence to this
principle, it adds, 'provides a fundamental test as to what constitutes a
civilised society' (20).

Even euthanasia at the patient's explicit request is to be prohibited. The
right to personal autonomy is not absolute: 'It is valid only when it
recognises other moral values, especially the respect due to human life as
such, whether someone else's or one's own' (18). Moreover, the exercise of
autonomy has to be limited in order that human beings may live together in
reasonable harmony.

Allied to this principled objection to voluntary euthanasia are two other
objections which focus on the undesirable consequences of tolerating it.
First, that 'it would be difficult to be sure that requests for euthanasia
were truly voluntary and settled, even if safeguards were built into the
legislation, and not the result either of depression or of undue pressure
from other people' (21). Second, that it would result in a breakdown of
trust between doctor and patient (22).

It would be a grave error to perceive the Christian opposition to
euthanasia as a rejection of the problems of the terminally ill. The
submission notes that the hospice movement grew out of the concerns of
Christians that people should be helped to die with dignity and it urges
that the lessons learned in hospices should be applied throughout the
health service to all dying people (23). It concludes that it is killing,
rather than caring, which denies the dignity of the dying.

Conclusion

Five main conclusions may be drawn about euthanasia in Buddhism and
Christianity. First, despite the widely different cultural background and
theological presuppositions informing both religious traditions, there is a
striking similarity in their opposition to the intentional killing of
patients. Secondly, this opposition is not coincidental but derives from
their shared rejection of consequentialist reasoning in favour of an
ethical approach grounded in a respect for human life as a basic as opposed
to an instrumental good. Thirdly, notwithstanding this shared absolute
opposition to euthanasia, both religions teach that life is not an absolute
value to be preserved at all costs and both emphasise the transistory
nature of earthly existence. Fourthly, the remarkable consensus between
these major but disparate religious traditions calls into question
prevalent assumptions about the impossibility of moral consensus in the
modern world. Finally, the common conclusions identified by this
investigation of the issue of euthanasia lends support to the conviction
articulated in the declaration of the Parliament of the World's Religions
that a common set of core values may be found in the teachings of the world
religions.

Key words

Death and dying; religious ethics.

References and notes

(1) Kung H and Kuschel K J, eds. A global ethic. The declaration of the
parliament of the world's religions. London: SCM Press, 1993: 14. Other
recent discussions include Runzo J, ed. Ethics, religion and the good
society: new directions in a pluralistic world, Louisville: John Knox
Press, 1992; Outka G, Reeder J P, eds. Prospects for a common morality,
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993. A selection from the speeches
made at the first parliament in 1893 may be found in Seager R H, ed. The
dawn of religious pluralism. Voices from the world's parliament of
religions, 1893. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1993. The declaration is
not, of course, a comprehensive exposition of the views of the signatories.
Some find the declaration incomplete in certain respects. See, for example,
Waldau P. Beyond praise of the 'declaration of the parliament of the
world's religions'. Studies in interreligious dialogue 1995; 5: 76-89.

(2) Toynbee A. Christianity among the religions of the world London: OUP,
1948:14. See also Keown D. Christian ethics in the light of Buddhist
ethics. Expository times 1995; 106, 5: 132-137.

(3) There are many schools of Buddhism and no central authority on matters
of doctrine. There is, however, a consensus on ethics among the main
schools. For the purposes of this article the Theravada School, which is
the oldest and most orthodox of the surviving traditions, is taken as
representative of the Buddhist position.

(4) See Keown D, The nature of Buddhist ethics. London: Macmillan, 1992.

(5) The Buddhist term is prajna which might be translated as 'rational
insight'. Like the Greek sophia, prajna denotes the cognitive faculty whose
function is the intuitive apprehension of truth. Prajna is not a
self-validating mystical intuition and is always grounded in, and
justifiable through, reason.

(6) A fuller discussion of these matters may be found in Keown D.d
bioethics. London: Macmillan, 1995: ch 1.

(7) For a fuller discussion see reference (6): Buddhism and bioethics:
21-36.

(8) Secondary literature on the subject is also scant. The most useful
article to date is Florida R E. Buddhist approaches to euthanasia. Studies
in religion/sciences religieuses 1993; 22: 35-47, which contains references
to most of the available sources.

(9) The precept states: 'If any monk should intentionally deprive a human
being of life or look for a knife-wielder he commits the offence of defeat
(parajika) and is no longer in communion' (Vinaya iii.71). The instrument
used is of no significance: the embedded commentary explains that the
lethal instrument may be a knife, a dagger, an arrow, a cudgel, a stone, a
sword, poison or a rope (Vinaya iii.73).

(10) Even killing in self-defence appears to be ruled out (Anguttara.iv.
188).

(11) Vinaya.ii.79.

(12) Vinaya.ii.86.

(13) In Buddhism, as in other religions, there exists the category of mots
voluntaria religiosa. This relates to cases where pious individuals or
saints, often under the influence of religious zeal, sacrifice their lives
for some religious end. Three notable cases are found in the Pali canon,
and many more (often fictitious) are scattered throughout later literature.
Although these examples are sometimes thought to show that Buddhism
condones suicide (and would therefore invalidate the principle stated
above) we think it would be unwise to draw normative conclusions from these
examples, especially since suicide is elsewhere clearly prohibited (for
example by the First Precept and also by the Monastic Rule, as seen above).
A brief discussion of the anomalous category of voluntary religious death
and its implications for ethics will be found in Buddhism and bioethics:
58-60. For a discussion of voluntary death in the context of another Indian
tradition, Jainism, see Bilimoria P. The Jaina ethic of voluntary death.
Bioethics 1992; 6: 330-355. With reference to Judaism and Christianity see
Droge A J, Tabor J D. A noble death: suicide and martyrdom among Christians
and Jews in antiquity. San Francisco: Harper Collins, 1991. With reference
to classical antiquity see van Hooff A J L. From autothanasia to suicide.
Self-killing in classical antiquity. London: Routledge, 1990.

(14) The Holy Bible. Letter of Paul to the Romans, 3:8.

(15) See, for example, Grisez G. Against consequential-ism. American
journal of jurisprudence 1978; 23: 21-73; Finnis J M. Fundamentals of
ethics. Oxford: OUP, 1983: ch IV.

(16) Joint Submission of the Anglican and Catholic Bishops to the House of
Lords Select Committee on Medical Ethics. Euthanasia - no! London: The
Incorporated Catholic Truth Society, 1993: para 3.

(17) See reference (16): para 13.

(18) See reference (16): para 8.

(19) See reference (16): para 14.

(20) See reference (16): para 4.

(21) See reference (16): para 12.

(22) See reference (16): para 17.

(23) See reference (16): paras 20-21.


没有相关内容

欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn


            在线投稿

------------------------------ 权 益 申 明 -----------------------------
1.所有在佛教导航转载的第三方来源稿件,均符合国家相关法律/政策、各级佛教主管部门规定以及和谐社会公序良俗,除了注明其来源和原始作者外,佛教导航会高度重视和尊重其原始来源的知识产权和著作权诉求。但是,佛教导航不对其关键事实的真实性负责,读者如有疑问请自行核实。另外,佛教导航对其观点的正确性持有审慎和保留态度,同时欢迎读者对第三方来源稿件的观点正确性提出批评;
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。