2025濠电姷鏁告慨鐑藉极閸涘﹥鍙忛柣鎴f閺嬩線鏌涘☉姗堟敾闁告瑥绻橀弻鐔虹磼閵忕姵鐏嶉梺绋块椤︻垶鈥﹂崸妤佸殝闂傚牊绋戦~宀€绱撴担鍝勭彙闁搞儜鍜佸晣闂佽瀛╃粙鎺曟懌闁诲繐娴氶崢濂告箒濠电姴锕ら幊搴㈢閹灔搴ㄥ炊瑜濋煬顒€鈹戦垾宕囧煟鐎规洜鍠栭、姗€鎮欏顔锯偓鎾⒒閸屾瑧顦﹂柟璇х節閹兘濡疯瀹曞弶鎱ㄥ璇蹭壕閻庢鍠栭…鐑藉极閹邦厼绶炲┑鐘插閸氬懘姊绘担鐟邦嚋缂佽鍊歌灋妞ゆ挾鍊e☉銏犵妞ゆ挾濮烽敍婊堟⒑缂佹ê濮﹂柛鎾寸懇瀹曟繈濡堕崱娆戭啎缂佺虎鍙冮ˉ鎾跺姬閳ь剟鎮楀▓鍨灈妞ゎ厾鍏橀獮鍐閵堝懎绐涙繝鐢靛Т鐎氼喛鍊撮梻鍌氬€风粈渚€骞夐敓鐘茬闁糕剝绋戝婵囥亜閺冨倻鎽傞柛鐔锋噽缁辨捇宕掑顑藉亾閹间礁纾归柣鎴eГ閸ゅ嫰鏌ら幖浣规锭闁搞劍姊归妵鍕箻閸楃偟浠奸梺鎼炲妼閸婂潡寮诲☉銏╂晝闁挎繂妫涢ˇ銉╂⒑閽樺鏆熼柛鐘崇墵瀵寮撮悢铏诡啎闂佺粯鍔﹂崜姘舵偟閺囥垺鈷戠紒瀣儥閸庡繑淇婇锝囩疄鐎殿喛顕ч埥澶婎潩椤愶絽濯伴梻浣告啞閹稿棝鍩€椤掆偓鍗遍柛顐g箥濞撳鏌曢崼婵囧殗闁绘稒绮撻弻鐔煎礄閵堝棗顏�4闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄥジ鏌熼惂鍝ョМ闁哄矉缍侀、姗€鎮欓幖顓燁棧闂備線娼уΛ娆戞暜閹烘缍栨繝闈涱儐閺呮煡鏌涘☉鍗炲妞ゃ儲鑹鹃埞鎴炲箠闁稿﹥顨嗛幈銊╂倻閽樺锛涢梺缁樺姉閸庛倝宕戠€n喗鐓熸俊顖濆吹濠€浠嬫煃瑜滈崗娑氭濮橆剦鍤曢柟缁㈠枛椤懘鏌嶉埡浣告殲闁绘繃娲熷缁樻媴閽樺-鎾绘煥濮橆厹浜滈柨鏃囶嚙閺嬨倗绱掓潏銊︻棃鐎殿喗鎸虫慨鈧柍閿亾闁归绮换娑欐綇閸撗呅氬┑鐐叉嫅缁插潡寮灏栨闁靛骏绱曢崢閬嶆⒑閸濆嫬鏆婇柛瀣尰缁绘盯鎳犻鈧弸娑㈡煟濞戝崬娅嶇€殿喕绮欓、妯款槼闁哄懏绻堝娲濞戞艾顣哄┑鐐额嚋缁茶法鍒掗鐔风窞濠电姴瀛╃€靛矂姊洪棃娑氬婵☆偅绋掗弲鍫曟焼瀹ュ棛鍘遍柣搴秵閸撴瑦绂掗柆宥嗙厵妞ゆ洖妫涚弧鈧繝纰夌磿閸忔﹢宕洪敓鐘茬<婵犲﹤鍟粻娲⒒閸屾瑧顦﹂柟纰卞亜鐓ら柕濞炬櫅绾剧粯绻涢幋娆忕仼闁绘帒鐏氶妵鍕箳閸℃ぞ澹曟繝鐢靛Л閸嬫捇姊洪鈧粔鎾倿閸偁浜滈柟鍝勭Х閸忓矂鏌涢悢鍝ュ弨闁哄瞼鍠栧畷娆撳Χ閸℃浼�5闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄥジ鏌熼惂鍝ョМ闁哄矉缍侀、姗€鎮欓幖顓燁棧闂備線娼уΛ娆戞暜閹烘缍栨繝闈涱儐閺呮煡鏌涘☉鍗炲妞ゃ儲鑹鹃埞鎴炲箠闁稿﹥顨嗛幈銊╂倻閽樺锛涢梺缁樺姉閸庛倝宕戠€n喗鐓熸俊顖濆吹濠€浠嬫煃瑜滈崗娑氭濮橆剦鍤曢柟缁㈠枛椤懘鏌嶉埡浣告殲闁绘繃鐗犲缁樼瑹閳ь剟鍩€椤掑倸浠滈柤娲诲灡閺呭爼骞嶉鍓э紲濡炪倖娲栧Λ娑㈠礆娴煎瓨鎳氶柡宥庣亹瑜版帗鏅查柛顐ゅ櫏娴犫晛顪冮妶鍡樷拹婵炶尙鍠庨~蹇撁洪鍛画闂佽顔栭崰妤呭箟婵傚憡鈷戦柤濮愬€曢弸鍌炴煕鎼达絾鏆鐐插暙椤粓鍩€椤掑嫬鏄ラ柨鐔哄Т缁€鍐┿亜韫囨挻锛旂紒杈ㄧ叀濮婄粯鎷呴搹鐟扮闂佽崵鍠嗛崹钘夌暦閹达箑绠荤紓浣贯缚閸橀亶姊洪棃娴ㄥ綊宕曢幎钘夋槬闁挎繂娲犻崑鎾斥枔閸喗鐏堝銈庡弮閺€杈ㄧ┍婵犲洤绠瑰ù锝呮憸閸樻悂姊虹粙鎸庢拱闁活収鍠氶懞杈ㄧ鐎n偀鎷绘繛杈剧到閹虫瑨銇愰幒鎴濈彉濡炪倖甯掗崐濠氭儗濞嗘挻鐓欓弶鍫熷劤閻︽粓鏌℃担绋库偓鍧楀蓟閵娾晜鍋嗛柛灞剧☉椤忥拷 闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄥジ鏌熼惂鍝ョМ闁哄矉缍侀、姗€鎮欓幖顓燁棧闂備線娼уΛ娆戞暜閹烘缍栨繝闈涱儐閺呮煡鏌涘☉鍗炲妞ゃ儲鑹鹃埞鎴炲箠闁稿﹥顨嗛幈銊╂倻閽樺锛涢梺缁樺姉閸庛倝宕戠€n喗鐓熸俊顖濆吹濠€浠嬫煃瑜滈崗娑氭濮橆剦鍤曢柟缁㈠枛椤懘鏌eΟ鑽ゅ灩闁搞儯鍔庨崢閬嶆煟韫囨洖浠滃褌绮欓幃锟狀敍濮樿偐鍞甸柣鐔哥懃鐎氼厾绮堥埀顒勬⒑鐎圭媭娼愰柛銊ユ健閵嗕礁鈻庨幋鐘碉紲闂佽鍎虫晶搴g玻濡ゅ懏鈷掑ù锝呮啞閸熺偞銇勯鐐搭棦鐎规洘锕㈤弫鎰板幢濞嗗苯浜炬繛宸簼閸婂灚顨ラ悙鑼虎闁告梹纰嶇换娑㈡嚑椤掆偓閳诲牏鈧娲橀崹鍧楃嵁濮椻偓閹虫粓妫冨☉娆戔偓顓㈡⒒娴e憡鍟炴繛璇х畵瀹曟粌鈽夐姀鈩冩珫濠电偞鍨崹娲煕閹达附鐓曟繛鎴炃氶惇瀣箾閸喐绀€闁宠鍨块幃娆戞嫚瑜戦崥顐︽⒑鐠団€虫灆闁告濞婇妴浣割潩鐠鸿櫣鍔﹀銈嗗坊閸嬫捇鏌i敐鍥у幋鐎规洖銈稿鎾Ω閿旇姤鐝滄繝鐢靛О閸ㄧ厧鈻斿☉銏╂晞闁糕剝銇涢弸宥夋倶閻愮紟鎺楀绩娴犲鐓熸俊顖濇娴犳盯鏌¢崱蹇旀珔闁宠鍨块、娆撴嚍閵夈儱鏀俊銈囧Х閸嬫盯鏁冮妷銉殫闁告洦鍨扮粻娑欍亜閹烘垵浜扮紒閬嶄憾濮婄粯鎷呯粵瀣秷閻庤娲橀敃銏ゃ€佸鎰佹▌闂佸搫琚崝鎴炰繆閸洖骞㈤柡鍥╁Х閻i箖姊绘笟鈧ḿ褔鎮ч崱娆屽亾濮樼厧鐏︾€规洘顨呴悾婵嬪礋椤掑倸骞堟繝鐢靛仜濡鎹㈤幋位澶愬閳╁啫寮挎繝鐢靛Т閹冲繘顢旈悩鐢电<閺夊牄鍔岀粭鎺楁懚閿濆鐓犲┑顔藉姇閳ь剚娲栭锝夊箮閼恒儮鎷绘繛杈剧到閹诧紕鎷归敓鐘崇厓鐎瑰嫭澹嗘晶锔锯偓瑙勬礃閸ㄥ灝鐣烽悢纰辨晬婵炴垶眉濡叉劖淇婇悙顏勨偓鏍箰閻愵剚鍙忓瀣椤ユ艾霉閻樺樊鍎愰柣鎾存礋閹﹢鎮欓幓鎺嗘寖闂佺懓鍟垮Λ娆撳Φ閸曨垰妫樻繛鍡欏亾閳诲牓姊洪崫鍕拱缂佸鎹囬崺鈧い鎺戯功缁夌敻鏌涚€n亝鍣归柣锝呭槻閻f繈宕熼鍌氬箰闂佽绻掗崑娑欐櫠娴犲鐓″鑸靛姈閻撶喖鏌ㄥ┑鍡橆棤缂佺姷鍋ら弻娑㈠煘閹傚濠碉紕鍋戦崐鏍暜閹烘柡鍋撳鐓庡濠㈣娲樼换婵嗩潩椤撶姴骞楅梻浣哥秺閸嬪﹪宕伴弽顓炵閻庯綆鍠楅悡鏇㈡倵閿濆簼绨婚柍褜鍓欏ḿ鈥愁嚕婵犳艾鍗抽柣鏃堫棑缁愮偤姊虹化鏇炲⒉閽冮亶鏌e┑鍥ㄧ婵﹨娅g槐鎺懳熺拠鍙夋闂備礁鎽滄慨鐢告偋閻樺樊鍤曞┑鐘崇閺呮悂鏌eΟ鍨毢闁稿﹦鍋ゅ铏光偓鍦У閵嗗啯淇婇悙鏉戠闁告帗甯″畷濂稿即閻斿弶瀚奸梻鍌欑贰閸嬪棝宕戝☉銏″殣妞ゆ牗绋掑▍鐘炽亜閺冨倹娅曠紒鈾€鍋撻梻渚€鈧偛鑻晶鎾煛鐏炶姤顥滄い鎾炽偢瀹曘劑顢涘顑洖鈹戦敍鍕杭闁稿﹥鐗滈弫顔界節閸ャ劌娈戦梺鍓插亝濞叉牠鎮块鈧弻锛勪沪鐠囨彃濮曢梺缁樻尰閻熲晠寮诲☉銏犵婵炲棗绻嗛崑鎾诲冀椤愮喎浜炬慨妯煎亾鐎氾拷闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄧ粯銇勯幒瀣仾闁靛洤瀚伴獮鍥敍濮f寧鎹囬弻鐔哥瑹閸喖顬堝銈庡亝缁挸鐣烽崡鐐嶆棃鍩€椤掑嫮宓佸┑鐘插绾句粙鏌涚仦鎹愬闁逞屽墰閹虫捇锝炲┑瀣╅柍杞拌兌閻ゅ懐绱撴担鍓插剱妞ゆ垶鐟╁畷銉р偓锝庡枟閻撴洘銇勯幇闈涗簼缂佽埖姘ㄧ槐鎾诲礃閳哄倻顦板┑顔硷龚濞咃綁骞忛悩璇茶摕闁靛鍠掗崑鎾澄旈崨顔惧幈濠碘槅鍨靛畷鐢告儗閹烘柡鍋撶憴鍕闁搞劌娼¢悰顔嘉熼懖鈺冿紲濠碘槅鍨抽崢褔鐛崼銉︹拻濞达絽鎲¢幆鍫熺箾鐏炲倸鐏茬€规洘绻勬禒锕傚礈瑜滃ú鎼佹⒑缂佹ê濮夐柛搴涘€濋幃锟犲Ψ閿斿墽顔曢梺鐟邦嚟閸嬬喖骞婇崨顔剧闁圭粯甯為幗鐘绘煙娓氬灝濡界紒缁樼箞瀹曟﹢鍩炴径姝屾闂傚倷娴囬鏍窗濮樿泛绀傛俊顖欒閸ゆ洟鏌ょ粙璺ㄤ粵闁稿海鍠栭弻鐔兼倷椤掍胶绋囬梺浼欑畳娴滎剛妲愰幘璇茬<婵﹩鍏橀崑鎾搭槹鎼淬埄鍋ㄩ梺璺ㄥ枔婵挳姊婚娑栦簻闁哄洦顨呮禍楣冩倵鐟欏嫭绀€缂傚秴锕ら悾閿嬬附缁嬪灝宓嗛梺缁樺姉閺佹悂寮抽锔解拻濞达綀濮ょ涵鍫曟煕閻樿櫕灏伴柟渚垮姂楠炴﹢顢欓懖鈺婃敤闂備浇顫夐崕鍏兼叏閵堝鍋傞煫鍥ㄧ〒閸欐捇鏌涢妷锝呭姎闁告柣鍊楅惀顏堝箚瑜庨崑銉╂煛鐏炲墽鈽夐摶锝夋煕韫囨挸鎮戞慨锝呯墕閳规垿顢欑涵宄板缂備緡鍣崹宕囧垝椤撱垺鍋勯柣鎾虫捣閸婄偤鎮峰⿰鍐i悗闈涘悑閹棃鏁愰崶鈺嬬闯濠电偠鎻徊浠嬪箹椤愶絿澧¢梻鍌欑劍閹爼宕濈仦缁撶細闁跨喓濮寸粻鏍归崗鍏煎剹闁轰礁锕﹂惀顏堝箯瀹€鍕懙閻庣偣鍊栧钘夘潖濞差亝鐒婚柣鎰蔼鐎氭澘顭胯椤曨參鍩€椤掍緡鍟忛柛鐘崇墵閳ワ箓鎮滈挊澶嬬€梺褰掑亰閸樿偐娆㈤悙缈犵箚妞ゆ牗绮庣敮娑欑箾閸涱厾效婵﹦绮幏鍛存惞閻熸壆顐奸梻浣规偠閸旀垵岣胯閸欏懘姊洪棃娑氬婵☆偅鐟╁畷锝堢疀閺冨倻顔曢梺鐟扮摠閻熴儵鎮橀鍫熺厓闂佸灝顑呴悘瀛樻叏婵犲啯銇濇い銏℃礋婵″爼宕ㄩ鍌涘礋闂傚倷绀侀崥瀣渻閸ф鍨傞梺顒€绉撮悿楣冩煕椤愶絾澶勯柡浣革躬閺屾盯骞樺Δ鈧幏鎴犳閹惰姤鐓熼幖杈剧磿閻n參鏌涙惔銊ゆ喚妤犵偛绻橀獮瀣攽閹邦剚娅婇梻渚€娼чˇ顓㈠磿閹惰棄姹查柛鈩冪⊕閻撱儲绻濋棃娑欘棡妞ゃ儲绮嶉妵鍕即閻旇櫣鐓傜紓浣介哺鐢偟妲愰幒鎳崇喖鎳栭埡鍐╂濠碉紕鍋戦崐銈夊磻閸涱垱宕查柛顐犲劘閳ь兛绀佽灃闁告侗鍘鹃敍婊堟⒑闂堟稓澧曢柟鍐茬箻瀵娊鍩¢崨顔规嫽闂佺ǹ鏈懝楣冨焵椤掆偓閸㈡煡婀侀梺鎼炲劀閳ь剟寮搁弽顓熺厸闁搞儯鍎遍悘鈺呮⒒閸屻倕鐏﹂柡灞诲姂瀵挳鎮欏ù瀣壕闁告縿鍎虫稉宥嗐亜閺嶎偄浠﹂柣鎾卞劦閺岋綁寮撮悙娴嬪亾閸︻厸鍋撳鐐3闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄥジ鏌熼惂鍝ョМ闁哄矉缍侀、姗€鎮欓幖顓燁棧闂備線娼уΛ娆戞暜閹烘缍栨繝闈涱儐閺呮煡鏌涘☉鍗炲妞ゃ儲鑹鹃埞鎴炲箠闁稿﹥顨嗛幈銊╂倻閽樺锛涢梺缁樺姉閸庛倝宕戠€n喗鐓熸俊顖濆吹濠€浠嬫煃瑜滈崗娑氭濮橆剦鍤曢柟缁㈠枛椤懘鏌嶉埡浣告殲闁绘繃娲熷缁樻媴閽樺-鎾绘煥濮橆厹浜滈柨鏃囶嚙閺嬨倗绱掓潏銊︻棃鐎殿喗鎸虫慨鈧柍閿亾闁归绮换娑欐綇閸撗呅氬┑鐐叉嫅缁插潡寮灏栨闁靛骏绱曢崢閬嶆⒑閸濆嫬鏆婇柛瀣尰缁绘盯鎳犻鈧弸娑㈡煟濞戝崬娅嶇€殿喕绮欓、妯款槼闁哄懏绻堝娲濞戞艾顣哄┑鐐额嚋缁茶法鍒掗鐔风窞濠电姴瀛╃€靛矂姊洪棃娑氬婵☆偅绋掗弲鍫曟焼瀹ュ棛鍘遍柣搴秵閸撴瑦绂掗柆宥嗙厵妞ゆ洖妫涚弧鈧繝纰夌磿閸忔﹢宕洪敓鐘茬<婵犲﹤鍟粻娲⒒閸屾瑧顦﹂柟纰卞亜鐓ら柕濞炬櫅绾剧粯绻涢幋娆忕仼闁绘帒鐏氶妵鍕箳閸℃ぞ澹曟繝鐢靛Л閸嬫捇姊洪鈧粔鎾倿閸偁浜滈柟鍝勭Х閸忓矂鏌涢悢鍝ュ弨闁哄瞼鍠栧畷娆撳Χ閸℃浼�8闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閹冣挃闁硅櫕鎹囬垾鏃堝礃椤忎礁浜鹃柨婵嗙凹缁ㄥジ鏌熼惂鍝ョМ闁哄矉缍侀、姗€鎮欓幖顓燁棧闂備線娼уΛ娆戞暜閹烘缍栨繝闈涱儐閺呮煡鏌涘☉鍗炲妞ゃ儲鑹鹃埞鎴炲箠闁稿﹥顨嗛幈銊╂倻閽樺锛涢梺缁樺姉閸庛倝宕戠€n喗鐓熸俊顖濆吹濠€浠嬫煃瑜滈崗娑氭濮橆剦鍤曢柟缁㈠枛椤懘鏌嶉埡浣告殲闁绘繃鐗犲缁樼瑹閳ь剟鍩€椤掑倸浠滈柤娲诲灡閺呭爼骞嶉鍓э紲濡炪倖娲栧Λ娑㈠礆娴煎瓨鎳氶柡宥庣亹瑜版帗鏅查柛顐ゅ櫏娴犫晛顪冮妶鍡樷拹婵炶尙鍠庨~蹇撁洪鍛画闂佽顔栭崰妤呭箟婵傚憡鈷戦柤濮愬€曢弸鍌炴煕鎼达絾鏆鐐插暙椤粓鍩€椤掑嫬鏄ラ柨鐔哄Т缁€鍐┿亜韫囨挻锛旂紒杈ㄧ叀濮婄粯鎷呴搹鐟扮闂佽崵鍠嗛崹钘夌暦閹达箑绠荤紓浣贯缚閸橀亶姊洪棃娴ㄥ綊宕曢幎钘夋槬闁挎繂娲犻崑鎾斥枔閸喗鐏堝銈庡弮閺€杈ㄧ┍婵犲洤绠瑰ù锝呮憸閸樻悂姊虹粙鎸庢拱闁活収鍠氶懞杈ㄧ鐎n偀鎷绘繛杈剧到閹虫瑨銇愰幒鎴濈彉濡炪倖甯掗崐濠氭儗濞嗘挻鐓欓弶鍫熷劤閻︽粓鏌℃担绋库偓鍧楀蓟閵娾晜鍋嗛柛灞剧☉椤忥拷
您现在的位置:佛教导航>> 五明研究>> 英文佛教>>正文内容

Reply to Paul Williams

       

发布时间:2009年04月18日
来源:不详   作者:Mark Siderits
人关注  打印  转发  投稿


·期刊原文
Reply to Paul Williams
By Mark Siderits
Philosophy East and West
Vol. 50, No. 3 (July 2000)
pp. 453-459
Copyright 2000 by University of Hawaii Press
Hawaii, USA

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

p. 453 Reply to Paul Williams Philosophy East and West, Vol. 50, No. 3 (July 2000)

There is much in Paul Williams' response to my review of his book to which I might reply, but I fear the debate may already be too protracted. So I shall take this opportunity just to try to clarify some key claims of mine about which I think Williams might be confused, and then leave it to the reader to decide where the truth lies. Since Williams has made it fairly clear where he stands, perhaps I should begin by indicating my own (present) views concerning the larger context in which our dispute is located. I do not think the Reductionist project -- reducing persons to a wholly impersonal causal series of psychophysical elements -- can ultimately be made to work. At the same time, I believe that Reductionism has the resources to answer the objections that its many critics, such as Williams, raise. The Reductionist view of persons is also, I think, compatible with at least two different sorts of ontology: the mental/material (nāma/rūpa) dualism of early Buddhism and Abhidharma and the naturalistic physicalism of much of contemporary analytic philosophy. Reductionism is likewise compatible both with belief in rebirth and with its denial. The real difficulty I see for Reductionism lies in answering the far more fundamental challenge of the Mādhyāmikas. (Unlike Williams, I do not think the Madhyamaka claim that nothing bears its own essential nature is incoherent, or tantamount to metaphysical nihilism.) Yet I suspect that the key to understanding the bodhisattva's compassion may lie in seeing that the Madhyamaka critique does not undermine all the consequences of Reductionism. So I think it is worth investigating whether there is a plausible reading of Śāntideva's argument that makes more philosophical sense than Williams sees in it.

Rebirth and Identity
This is not the place to get into a lengthy battle over the meaning of "neither the same nor different" in the Indian Buddhist tradition, but let me say a few words about my own understanding of the expression as it occurs at Milindapañha 40. Like many other Buddhologists, Williams understands the expression to involve equivocation between numerical and qualitative identity. I claim instead that the expression is univocal, involving just numerical identity. (For a clear instance of this use,

p. 454 Reply to Paul Williams Philosophy East and West, Vol. 50, No. 3 (July 2000)

see Tattvasaṅgraha 338-342.) This means that in my reading, the expression involves a (usually implicit) sortal term: x and y are neither the same K nor distinct Ks. So when Nāgasena says that adult and infant are neither the same nor different, I take him to mean that they are not the same person and also not distinct persons. Of course, this bivalence failure seems so odd that we are immediately tempted to explain it away as involving equivocation. (Though we might not be so tempted if we recalled the case of the fire that had gone out, yet had not gone north or south or east or west.) Yet when Milinda claims that adult and infant are numerically distinct persons, Nāgasena gives various reasons why this claim should be rejected, and states instead that adult and infant are numerically identical persons. To explain all this he gives the analogy of the one light that shone all night. The flame of the first watch is numerically distinct from that of the second watch, and so forth, and it is the flame that does the illuminating at any moment, yet we would still say it is one light that shone all night. This is because 'light' (padīpa) is a convenient designation for a causal series of flames. The ultimate truth is that there is a series of such flames, each existing for a moment, then going out of existence, but giving rise to a successor. This situation may be described, at the level of conventional truth, as one light shining all night. But since the use of convenient designations is banned from the ultimate truth (because they lead to reification), we may not say either that ultimately the first flame and the last flame are (stages of) the same light or that they are distinct lights.

The bivalence failure is just a dramatic way of putting the point that ultimately an enduring light is a mere conceptual fiction and so not ultimately real. When applied to the case of persons, the lesson is that ultimately there is just the causal series of psychophysical elements, but that we have learned to use the convenient designation 'person' for such a series, so that conventionally the adult is the same person as the infant, though ultimately they are neither the same person not distinct persons -- once again, for the simple reason that the person is a mere conceptual fiction.

I take this account to be meant to apply to the case of rebirth as well, at least for early Buddhism and Abhidharma. So, ultimately, the psychophysical elements at rebirth are not the same person as those at the prior death, nor are they distinct persons, yet conventionally we may say that these are two stages in the existence of the same person. This is conventionally true because the causal link between the earlier and later psychophysical elements is of the same sort as that which typically obtains between the elements at one stage in a life and the elements at a later stage in that life. Now one reason I think this is the view of early Buddhism and Abhidharma is that when the Buddha teaches karma and rebirth to the laity (in the neyārtha texts), he seems to be appealing to his audience's self-concern. He appears to be saying that just as one ordinarily seeks to maximize the well-being of the later stages of oneself in this life, so the truth about rebirth shows that one should exercise equal prudential concern with regard to future lives as well, and the truth about karma shows how best to do so. Considerations of prudential concern would have no force here unless the audience were being led to believe that rebirth involves what would conventionally be called the same person.

p. 455 Reply to Paul Williams Philosophy East and West, Vol. 50, No. 3 (July 2000)

Like Williams, I find it hard to think of cockroaches as persons. Still, if I believed that my existence involves the continued existence of a witness self (like the sākṣin of Sāṃkhya and Advaita), and I had reason to believe that cockroaches are at least minimally conscious, then I might have to entertain the possibility that rebirth as a cockroach could occur. Philosophical arguments sometimes lead to counterintuitive results. For a Buddhist Reductionist, the continued existence of a person will, I think, require a far more complex mentality than it seems likely that a cockroach enjoys. A plausible account would, I believe, require that the reborn being have the capacity, at some stage of its life, to remember at least the more significant experiences of the prior life (though this capacity need not be exercised). The fact that a human embryo cannot be said to have this capacity proves nothing. While I am under total anesthesia I am incapable of remembering the experiences of the person who signed the patient-consent form, yet this does not render the surgeon guilty of operating on a non-consenting patient.

Coming to be a Construction
First, I think it crucially important to point out that I do not think 'person' is an "ultimately arbitrary convention." A convention, yes, but a convenient one -- that is, one that reflects certain interests, in this case an interest in minimizing overall suffering. I take the Buddhist Reductionist view to be that adopting this convention does tend to promote this end. Hence Nāgasena's references to punishing the criminal and rewarding the student, in his refutation of Milinda's view that adult and infant are distinct persons. For the Buddhist, the difficulty is just that our tendency to reify leads, when we employ this convention, to a belief in a person existing over and above the psychophysical elements, hence to clinging, hence to alienation and despair. Thus our adopting the convention in an unreflective way can diminish some kinds of suffering, but bring about other sorts. It also leads (and I take this to be the point of Śāntideva's argument) to our seeing a deep difference between suffering occurring in this causal series and suffering occurring in others. So our adopting the convention in an unreflective way causes us to miss many opportunities to alleviate the suffering around us.

As evidence for the claim that personhood is a construction, I pointed out that children must be taught to identify with past and future stages of the causal series. [1] As often happens at this point in the debate, Williams invokes biology in response. I don't think this will help. The naturalistically inclined Reductionist will agree that when spiders engage in behavior that promotes their long-term interest, it is reasonable to explain this by appealing to forces of natural selection that resulted in their having a certain sort of hardwiring. But humans are quite different. Because human infants are born premature by mammalian standards, their brains at birth are not hardwired for the more complex behavioral repertoires needed for survival. Instead, the neural structures that support cognition and affect are formed in interaction with the social environment during the first several years of life. Among the earliest bands of proto-hominids, some provided their young with social environments that fostered

p. 456 Reply to Paul Williams Philosophy East and West, Vol. 50, No. 3 (July 2000)

the development of habits of long-term prudential concern: the identification of the individual with their past and future stages, and dispositions to behave in ways that maximized well-being over the life span. Those that did this are our ancestors.

Finally, a Reductionist could agree that while children must typically be taught that three plus three equals six, this is not a socially constructed fact. A Reductionist can be a metaphysical realist about (ultimate) truth. Learning to think of oneself as a person is different, though, just as is learning to think of oneself as a certain sort of person. In a racist society, learning to think of oneself as belonging to a particular race can have significant consequences. Some facts only come into existence through certain social practices.

A Painful Subject?
First, a point of clarification about pains. The Reductionist does not deny that the occurrence of a pain sensation naturally causes behavior that aims at dispelling that pain; this does not require belief in personhood. What is distinctive about persons is their capacity to anticipate future pains and seek to prevent their occurrence, which is accomplished through the processes of identification and appropriation. Now the Reductionist will gladly concede that conventionally, pains have subjects. Coming to be a person means coming to think of some pains as occurring to the person who is me, others as occurring to other beings. The question at issue between Williams and the Reductionist is whether it is ultimately true that pains must have subjects. This the Reductionist must deny. Their argument for altruism depends on the claim that the conventional assignment of pains to persons is merely a useful way of trying to maximize impersonal welfare, and one that can be improved upon by taking the boundaries between persons less seriously. If it is ultimately true that pains must have subjects, this argument will fail.

I hope I was not being unfair to Williams when I attributed a functionalist view of pain to him. I did so because I was looking for some reason to support his claim that pains ultimately require subjects. Adverbial and event analyses of pain do not show this; the subject supplied in such analyses may well disappear under further analysis. And practitioners of vipaśyanā meditation will agree with Williams' characterization of pain's intrinsic nature, yet insist that there can be subjectless pains. Since Williams knows that one cannot simply rely on one's intuitions in these matters, I took those passages that suggested a functional analysis to constitute an implicit defense of his claim. Williams is right to want to distance himself from functionalism. It is true that the functionalist can be a reductionist and not an eliminativist about pain (what Williams calls a soft functionalist). But then the phenomenal properties of pain will (reductively) supervene on facts about the organism and its evolutionary history, and pain itself will lack independent causal and explanatory power. Pain will be only conventionally real, not ultimately real. So this won't fit with the claim that pain ultimately requires a subject.

I agree that it is not immediately obvious how to go about constructing sets of psychophysical elements that are maximally causally connected. Since I intend to

p. 457 Reply to Paul Williams Philosophy East and West, Vol. 50, No. 3 (July 2000)

deal with this more fully elsewhere, I appreciate Williams' critical comments. But if we are to be nāma-rūpa dualists, there is no difficulty individuating the mental elements based on their causal connections with the physical ones. The Buddha did, after all, hold that the nāma skandhas originate in dependence on sense-object-contact events, which are physical in nature. And, sadly, Williams' clever example of the miscreant who seeks to escape punishment by undergoing fission has been anticipated. [2] I agree, though, that fission raises difficult questions for the theory of karmic punishment. Buddhist ethics contains some elements suggestive of retributivism, and these are incompatible with Buddhist Reductionism.

Foggy Mountain Breakdown
I characterized the Buddhist Reductionist as holding that wholes are ultimately unreal, and that only impartite entities and their properties ultimately exist. (I did not say that the Mādhyamika believes both of these things; they would, of course, deny the second.) According to this view there is a true answer to the question of whether or not there were pines on Mount Fuji before there were persons to observe them. But the answer depends on what the ultimate facts are, and the ultimate facts consist entirely of facts about impartite entities and their properties. If some such entities were arranged in the way that we would classify as pines growing on Mount Fuji, then the answer is that the sentence 'Pines lived on Mount Fuji before Honshū was inhabited' is conventionally true.

Williams, with the Aristotelian, is willing to concede that the Reductionist view might be true of artifacts, but doubts it could be true of complex organisms like cows or trees. I think that the Reductionist side is supported by recent developments in biology, where, for instance, the reduction of embryology to biochemistry now appears feasible. [3] If all the facts concerning the formation of the embryo (such as differentiation of tissue types to form different organs) can be explained in terms of the biochemical properties of the gamete pair and the embryonic environment, then the organism as a whole lacks autonomous explanatory power and is causally inert. Everyone presumably agrees that the ultimate parts making up the organism are real. By the principle of lightness, then, we should eliminate the organism from our ultimate ontology, at the same time acknowledging its usefulness for our conceptual economy by granting it conventional reality. This is the sort of argument Buddhist Reductionists have in mind when they deny the ultimate existence of partite things.

I suggested that sorites difficulties might supply another such argument. Williams responds that even if we cannot say just where Mount Everest or a patch of fog begins, the mountain and the fog are real for all that, since they have real effects: when I become lost in the fog on the mountain, I may fall over a cliff. But the Reductionist does not deny the existence of a mass of contiguous suspended water droplets in the vicinity of that mass of earth atoms conveniently designated 'Mount Everest.' And these entities, with these spatial properties, are all that is needed to explain my fall. The question is whether we should additionally posit the wholes, the fog and the mountain. The challenge for the realist about wholes that is raised by

p. 458 Reply to Paul Williams Philosophy East and West, Vol. 50, No. 3 (July 2000)

indeterminacy is that there will be sentences of the form 'An entity of sort K exists here' that will be neither true nor false. Descending from Mount Everest step by step, there will come a point where it is no longer true to say that we are on Mount Everest, but it is also not false. Worse yet, there is no determinate point at which we can say that it begins to be no longer true that we are on Mount Everest. Multivalent logics do not seem to help here. Nor does fuzzy set theory. As Williams points out, we expect sortals like 'fog' to behave this way, and we might even come to expect it of 'mountain.' This does not dispel the difficulty for the realist about wholes, though; it merely repeats it. If these are the names of real things, their use should not generate logical contradictions of the sort "It is not the case that we are on Mount Everest, but it is also not the case that we are not on Mount Everest." Real things should not occasion bivalence failure. [4] For the Reductionist, on the other hand, indeterminacy is not a problem. Our use of the convenient designation 'mountain' will naturally occasion truth-value gaps, since this is merely a rough-and-ready way of referring to a certain sort of arrangement of earth particles, and the exigencies of human communication require that all the details of the arrangement not be specified in advance. [5]

There is obviously much more that could be said on both sides of this debate, but I should stop here. Let me close by saying that I very much like Williams' notion of "analytic meditation." I don't think it is enough by itself to bring about the sort of enlightenment that Buddhists seek (though the other sort of meditation is not sufficient either). But it is, I think, necessary. For one must know the truth to attain enlightenment, and our best shot at attaining the truth about these matters comes through philosophical dialogue with those holding opposing views. Though I still disagree with Williams, I have learned much -- about ways in which my own views may require elaboration or modification to be defensible -- from our exchange. To engage in analytic meditation, one needs worthy opponents, people capable of raising embarrassing questions for one's favored theory. In this and in my initial piece I have given several references to recent work that I think creates difficulties for those taking Williams' line. I should do the same for those who favor the Reductionist line. One source that immediately comes to mind is the recent collection Reading Parfit, [6] especially the pieces by Blackburn, McDowell, and Johnston. But also worth considering is the classical Nyāya attack on Buddhist Reductionism, as presented in the work of Arindam Chakrabarti. [7]

Notes
1. For an excellent phenomenological account of the resulting habit of appropriating certain non-present states see Raymond Martin, Self-Concern (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), especially chapter 5.

2. David Wiggins, "Locke, Butler and the Stream of Consciousness," in The Identities of Persons, ed. Amelie O. Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976), pp. 139-173 at p. 146.

p. 459 Reply to Paul Williams Philosophy East and West, Vol. 50, No. 3 (July 2000)

3. See Alex Rosenberg, "Reductionism Redux: Computing the Embryo," Biology and Philosophy 12: 445-470.

4. See Terrence Horgan, "Robust Vagueness and the Forced-March Sorites Paradox," Philosophical Perspectives, ed. James E. Tomberlin (Atascadero, California: Ridgeview) 8 (1994): 159-188. Also Peter Unger, "There are no Ordinary Things," Synthese 41 (1979): 117-154.

5. Crispin Wright has an interesting discussion of the pragmatics of vague terms (though he reaches somewhat different conclusions) in his "Language Mastery and the Sorites Paradox," in Truth and Meaning: Essays in Semantics, ed. Gareth Evans and John McDowell (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976), pp. 223-247.

6. Reading Parfit, ed. Jonathan Dancy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997).

7. See especially, "I Touch What I Saw," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1992): 103-116.

没有相关内容

欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn


            在线投稿

------------------------------ 权 益 申 明 -----------------------------
1.所有在佛教导航转载的第三方来源稿件,均符合国家相关法律/政策、各级佛教主管部门规定以及和谐社会公序良俗,除了注明其来源和原始作者外,佛教导航会高度重视和尊重其原始来源的知识产权和著作权诉求。但是,佛教导航不对其关键事实的真实性负责,读者如有疑问请自行核实。另外,佛教导航对其观点的正确性持有审慎和保留态度,同时欢迎读者对第三方来源稿件的观点正确性提出批评;
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。