您现在的位置:佛教导航>> 五明研究>> 英文佛教>>正文内容

Samkara on the Question: Whose is Avidya

       

发布时间:2009年04月18日
来源:不详   作者:Daniel H. H. Ingalls
人关注  打印  转发  投稿


·期刊原文
Samkara on the Question: Whose is Avidya?[*]
By Daniel H. H. Ingalls
Philosophy East and West
V. 3, No. 1 (1953)
pp. 69-72
Copyright 1953 by University of Hawaii Press

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

 

 

p.69

The word "avidyaa," which is variously translated as ignorance, nescience, illusion, is one of the most important terms in the philosophy of `Sa^mkaraacaarya and his followers. It is by the concept of avidyaa that these monistic philosophers explain the apparent diversity of the world. They claim that in truth there is one indivisible reality,, that the experience we have of diversity is due simply to avidyaa.

Now, the use of this concept leads to a logical dilemma. If this avidyaa is a real entity, then monism ends. On the other hand, to say that it is an imaginary entity is to destroy the very doctrine of avidyaa. As Descartes could not doubt that he doubted, so the Kevalaadvaitins could not find illusion itself to be an illusion.

There are two ways out of this dilemma. One of them has been taken by most of `Sa^mkara's followers and has come to be known as the typical Kevalaadvaita point of view. In this system a new truth-value is set up, anirvaca.niiyatva, that which cannot be said to be either true or false. It is a direct consequence of the dilemma I have mentioned that the Kevalaadvaita developed a multivalue system of logic, the most widely accepted system of this sort that the world has known.

There is, however, another way out of the dilemma, that is, not by solving but by avoiding it. This was the way chosen by `Sa^mkaraacaarya himself. Most authorities on `Sa^mkara have overlooked the fact that he differs from his followers in this matter. The difference has recently been pointed out, however, by Paul Hacker in an article in ZDMG.[1] Hacker there considers only the Brahmasuutrabhaa.sya. I have thought it might be worth while here to make a cast, though it must be a very brief one, into other waters.

The premise from which all `Sa^mkara's arguments on the subject of avidyaa begin is this: One must realize that avidyaa is not an inherent characteristic of the self or soul. As soon as it is seen not properly to belong to the self,

______________________________________________________________________________________________
* This paper was read before the American Oriental Society in Boston, April 2, 1952.

1. Zeitschrift der Deutschen Morgenlandischen Gesellschaft, 100 (1950), 246-286.

 

 

p.70

the true nature of the self will be realized and mok.sa (release) will be obtained. The question of the exact modality of avidyaa is inconsequential. One is reminded of the words of another religious teacher of India. The Buddha was asked a number of metaphysical questions by the fool Malunkyaputta His answer was to liken Malunkyaputta to a man struck by an arrow, who would not let the surgeon draw the arrow till he discovered the name of the man who shot it and the wood of which it was made.

In at least three passages `Sa^mkara discusses the question: Whose is avidyaa? In each passage he denies the real connection of avidyaa with the self or soul but in none of these passages, it is worth noting, does he deny the reality of avidyaa itself.

In Brahmasuutrabhaa.sya IV.i.3 the synonym aprabodha (unenlightenment) is used in place of the commoner term. This is in order to obtain a rhetorical effect in answering the opponent:

Whose then is this unenlightenment, it may be asked. To which we reply: Yours, since you ask about it. But [says the opponent], according to scripture I am God Answer: If you are so enlightened as to know this, then you must know that unenlightenment is no one's.

Hacker well characterizes this passage as "not philosophically exact, but pedagogically impressive."

The same question is treated, but more philosophically and in considerably greater detail, in that commentary on the B.rhadaara.nyaka Upani.sad which is now definitely known to be by `Sa^mkara.[2] Here `Sa^mkara takes the pass; "brahmaiva san brahmaapyeti" (IV.i.6) as scriptural evidence of jiivanmukti, release before death. In support of his view he shows that release of the self implies no real change within it nor any change in such qualities as avidyaa which might have been supposed to have belonged to the self. For avidyaa never truly belongs to the self. To prove this, `Sa^mkara shows that one can be aware of avidyaa only as belonging to the category of things known, never as belonging to the category of knowers. That is, whatever awareness we have of avidyaa shows that it cannot be a part of the self. It cannot because, to use `Sa^mkara's term, it is a vi.saya, an object of knowledge.

The argument is first carried on briefly by means of a pun. The word viviktatas, distinctly, may mean distinctly, that is, clearly; or it may mean distinctly, that is, as something distinct or separate. "He who perceives avidyaa distinctly, like a pot, cannot possess avidyaa."

______________________________________________________________________________________________
2. Cf. Kathe Marschner, Zur Verfasserfrage des dem `Samkaracarya zugeschriebenen B.rhadaara.nyako- pani.sad-Bhaa.sya, typescript (Berlin: Alfred Lindner Verlag, 1933); also Paul Hacker, Untersuchungen uber Texte des fruhen Advaitavaata (Mainz: Ak. d. Wiss. und Lit. Abhardharma der geistes- und Sozialwissenschaftlichen Klasse, 1950), p. 1918.

 

 

p.71

The reason is obvious. One cannot possess a quality which is distinct or separate from oneself. But the opponent is soon placed in a still more difficult position:

But I do not know, says the opponent; I am a stupid man (mugdho 'smi). Surely this percept shows that I am in error through avidyaa. No, [says `Sa^mkara] because you have perceived it distinctly. One who perceives a fact distinctly cannot be in error concerning that fact. It is self-contradictory to say that a man both perceives a thing distinctly and is in error.

At this point `Sa^mkara stops playing with his opponent and comes to the heart of the matter:

You say that a man perceives that he does not know and that he is stupid. That is as much as to say that ignorance and stupidity are perceived by that perceiver, that they are objects (vi.saya) of perception, that they are an effect (karma). Then how can ignorance and stupidity, which are effects, be qualifications of the perceiver who is the effector?

Rather than pursue this passage to its conclusion, let me turn to the Giitaabhaa.sya. This also has generally been attributed to `Sa^mkara, and I see no reason to doubt the ascription.

In the long commentary on Giitaa XIII.2 `Sa^mkara raises the same question: Whose is avidyaa? But in the lines which follow, some new arguments are added. Granted that avidyaa is not essential to the self, it might be supposed even in a real sense to have some connection with the self. No, says `Sa^mkara, because such a connection can neither be perceived nor inferred. That it cannot be perceived is fairly obvious. I shall quote only the last part of the argument dealing with inference.

If your knowledge is by inference, how can you know the connections? At the time that you, the knower, know avidyaa, the thing which is known, you certainly cannot also know the connection between yourself and it, for avidyaa is related to the knower solely as being an object of his knowledge. Nor can one imagine a knower of the connection between the knower and the avidyaa nor a knowledge having such a connection for its content, for we should then have to admit an infinite series. If one's connection with the known is known by a knower, then another knower may be set up, and another knower of that, and of that, and so on to infinity. But if avidyaa is the known, or, for the matter of that, if anything else is, then the known is simply the known. Similarly, the knower is simply the knower; he cannot become the known. Such being the case, the self (k.setraj~na), which is the knower, is never affected by such entities as avidyaa and sorrow.

In all these passages one sees that `Sa^mkara never admits either horn of the dilemma. Avidyaa is never said to be real. It is never said to be unreal. But no new modality is set up to solve the difficulty. One may even state

 

 

p.72

it as likely that `Sa^mkara disapproved the postulation of a third truth-value. This is only a guess. But the concept is certainly as old as the time of `Sa^mkara[3] and one may hazard a second guess as to why he rejected it. If the characterizing of the phenomenal world as anirvaca.niiya makes the world no more real than it is in `Sa^rnkara's doctrine, it makes it a great deal less unreal. Such a characterization may well have seemed unsound to `Sa^mkara's intuition.

What `Sa^mkara does is to avoid the difficulty. He concentrates on what he considers the heart of the matter, the teaching that is necessary for the attainment of mok.sa. This teaching is that avidyaa, whatever its modality, is never truly connected with the self. Here, as in other differences that end be noticed between `Sa^rnkara and his disciples, one may say that `Sa^mkara's approach to truth is psychological and religious. His interest in metaphysics and logic is always subordinated to the center of his attention. His followers while deeply attracted by this attitude, were gradually forced to construct a metaphysical system that is in all respects logically coherent.

______________________________________________________________________________________________
3. As noted by Hacker (ZDMG 100.255 n.1) anirvaca.niiyatva in the sense of a third truth-value is found in Ma.n.danami`sra. In the rare instances where `Sa^mkara uses the word (e.g., on Brahma-suutra II, i. 27) it has quite a different meaning. It is there applied to naamaruupa, the cosmic stuff, in its unmanifested state where it cannot be said to be this or that, i.e., where it is undifferentiated. (Hacker, op. cit., p. 263)

没有相关内容

欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn


            在线投稿

------------------------------ 权 益 申 明 -----------------------------
1.所有在佛教导航转载的第三方来源稿件,均符合国家相关法律/政策、各级佛教主管部门规定以及和谐社会公序良俗,除了注明其来源和原始作者外,佛教导航会高度重视和尊重其原始来源的知识产权和著作权诉求。但是,佛教导航不对其关键事实的真实性负责,读者如有疑问请自行核实。另外,佛教导航对其观点的正确性持有审慎和保留态度,同时欢迎读者对第三方来源稿件的观点正确性提出批评;
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。