A Chinese madhyamaka theory of truth: The case of OF Chi-Tsang
·期刊原文
A CHINESE MADHYAMAKA THEORY OF TRUTH: THE CASE OF CHI-TSANG
By Ming-Wood Liu
Philosophy East and West
Volume 43, Number 4(October 1993)
Pp.649-673
(C) by University of Hawaii Press
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
P.649
Chi-tsang (549-623) was the key figure in the
revival of Chinese Madhyamaka in the late sixth
century, and his teaching is commonly acknowledged
to be the apex of the development of Madhyamaka
thought in China.(1) This essay attempts to examine
the conception of truth underlying a number of ideas
generally considered as central to Chi-tsang's
philosophy, including "refutation of falsehood"
(p'o-hsieh), "revelation of truth" (hsien-cheng),
and "two truths" (erh-ti).(2) But before entering
into these ideas, we shall take a brief look at one
idea which determines the overall direction of
Chi-tsang's thought and which constitutes the very
theoretical basis of his teaching of truth, namely,
the idea of nonattachment.
Nonattachment as the Central Spirit of Chi-tsang's
Teaching
Chi-tsang is very fond of quoting the words of
Fa-lang (507-581), his teacher, to support his own
theories. In the following resume which Chi-tsang
gives of Fa-lang's instruction, students are
enjoined to follow the rules of "nonabidingness"
(wu-chu) and "nonacquisitiveness (wu-te) in their
speech and thought:
Whenever our teacher, the Reverend [Fa-]lang,
ascended the hish seat and instructed his
followers, he often said: [Our] words should
take "nonabidingness" as the point of departure,
and [our] minds should take "nonacquisitiveness"
as the principal [guide]. Hence, the profound
suutras and eminent masters enlighten living
beings by making their minds free from
attachment. It is so because attachment is the
root of encumbrances. As the origin of all
sufferings is attachment, Buddhas of the three
periods (of past, present, and future) devise
sutras and lecture `saastras, all in order to
make the minds of sentient beings free from
attachment.(3)
Chi-tsang takes up Fa-lang's view of attachment as
the "root of encumbrances'' when he observes that
"the existence of dependence and attachment is the
root of various defilements" and when he disparages
those practitioners liable to the error of
attachment as "ignorant'' and "devoid of the [ture]
way and the [true] fruit."(4) Chi-tsang also follows
Fa-lang in considering the cultivation of
nonattachment as the principal objective of the
teaching of all Buddhist scriptures, when he makes
out that "nondependence" and "nonattachment" are the
main principles of all suutras and `saastras:
Buddhas of the three periods, for the sake of
sentient beings of the six ways whose minds are
attached,5 appear in the world to preach the
sutras. The "four catagories of enlightened
masters" (ssu-i k'ai-shih),(6) for the sake of
P.650
[those] Mahaayaana and Hiinayaana learners whose
minds are dependent, appear in the world to
compose the `saastras. Hence, dependence and
attachment are the roots of sa.msaara and
nondependence and nonattachment are the major
principles of the suutras and `saastras.(7)
In Chi-tsang's writings, nonattachment is
represented as the basis of deliverance and the
entrance to the true Way.s Lauded as the "one mark
and one taste" of the Buddha Dharma,(9) it is looked
upon as forming the very essence of the superior
Buddha-vehicle.(10)
The importance attributed to the practice of
nonattachment by Fa-lang and Chi-tsang is grounded
on the Buddhist scriptures. Its origin can be traced
back to the very beginning of the Buddhist religion,
when `Saakyamuni, prompted by the realization that
desire is the root of all ills,(11) formulated such
doctrines as the "five skandhas" and "non-self" with
a view to eliminating the attachment of sentient
beings to sa.msaaric existence.(12) The emphasis on
nonattachment in Buddhism came to a head in the
Praj~naapaaramitaa-suutras and the early Madhyamaka
works of Naagaarjuna and Naagaarjuna's followers.
These works exempted nothing, not even the cardinal
Buddhist ideals of nirvana and Buddhahood, from the
rule of abandonment.(13) Chi-tsang's clear knowledge
of the thorough form of nonattachment which the
Madhyamaka tradition advocates is clearly
demonstrated in the following comments he makes on
the purpose of Naagaarjuna's writings:
Further, the general purport of the works which
Naagaarjuna composed during his appearance in
the world is first of all to refute and to
eliminate all errors of acquisitiveness, until
they are totally done away with. Any mind with
the slightest [proclivity for] dependence and
any discourse with the smallest [sign of]
determinateness, whether they be Mahaayaana or
Hiinayaana, Buddhist or non-Buddhist, based upon
the words [of the scriptures] or created without
the support of the words [of the scriptures],
are all to be cleansed, until they are made
entirely pure. However, when the impure have
been got rid of, the pure also do not
remain.(14)
According to Chi-tsang, Naagaarjuna aimed to achieve
with his treatises the eradication of all forms of
acquisitions, including not only the eradication of
the acquisition of the thoughts and words of the
Hinayana and the non-Buddhists, but also the
eradication of the acquisition of the thoughts and
words of the Mahaayaana and the Buddhists. Hence, he
prescribed that the pure should be given up together
with the impure, for grasping at the pure is as
serious a mistake as grasping at the impure. Quoting
the words of Fa-lang, Chi-tsang laments how often
truth, wisdom, and meditation become additional
obstacles on the path of enlightenment due to the
deliberate frame of mind of the practitioners:
Further, whenever my teacher, the Reverend
Master of the Hsing-huang [Monastery], ascended
the high seat, he often said as follows:
Practitioners of
P.651
the Way want to forsake the false ways and seek
the True Way, and thus are bound by [their
longing for] the Way. Practitioners of
meditation [try to] stop disturbances and seek
calmness, and thus are bound by [their fondness
for] meditation. Pursuers of scholarship claim
that there is wisdom [to be cultivated], and
thus are bound by [their love of] wisdom. They
further say, "We should practice contemplating
[the truth of] nonorigination so as to eliminate
the mind of acquisition." As a consequence, they
are bound by [the idea of] nonorigination.
Living in the midst of bondages, they want to
abandon bondages, not really knowing that [their
attempts to abandon bondages] are all
[additional causes of] bondages.(15)
Among the objects of nonattachment cited by
Chi-tsang is the notion of nonattachment itself. So
Chi-tsang chides those practitioners who are
attached to the practice of nonattachment as blind
to the Buddha's real intention,(16) and warns his
readers not to adhere to the idea of
"non-acquisitiveness" as definitely correct:
If we definitely take "nonacquisitiveness" as
right, it would still be [a form of]
acquisitiveness and is not called
"nonacquisitiveness." Just the complete absence
of dependence is called
"nonacquisitiveness."(17)
In Chi-tsang's opinion, real abandonment is achieved
only when one abandons "abandonment" as well as
"procurement.'"(18)
Chi-Tsang's Concept of Truth as Nonattachment
A. Nonattachment as the Criterion of Truth. That
Chi-tsang's teaching of absolute nonattachment has a
direct bearing on his teaching of truth is testified
to by where Chi-tsang draws the line between the
true and the false:
If we harbor [the distinction between] Buddhist
and non-Buddhist and dwell upon [the division
between] Mahaayaana and Hiinayaana, we shall
fall into the falsehood of one-sidedness and
lose sight of the true principle.... Only the
simultaneous allaying of [the thoughts of]
Buddhist and non-Buddhist and the concurrent
subduing [of the ideas of] Mahaayaana and
Hiinayaana are known as the true principle.(19)
This passage links "falsehood" to the harboring, and
"truth" to the forsaking, of the distinction between
Hiinayaana and Mahaayaana, between Buddhist and
non-Buddhist, and so forth. Another passage
associates falsehood with acquisitiveness and truth
with nonacquisitiveness:
Falsehoods are innumerable, and truths are also
of many kinds. Roughly speaking, they do not
fall outside two categories: "with
acquisitiveness" and "without acquisitiveness."
Those [ideas] which are with acquisitiveness are
false and have to be refuted; those [ideas]
which are without acquisitiveness are true and
have to be expounded.(20)
P.652
In sum, as Chi-tsang sees it, truth rests entirely
upon nonattachment.
B. "Refutation of Falsehoods" /s Equivalent to
"Revelation of Truths" (P'o-hsieh chi hsien-cheng).
The implications of Chi-tsang's conception of truth
as nonattachment can be seen from Chi-tsang's
exposition of the two ideas of "refutation of
falsehoods" and "revelation of truths," which are
made out in Chi-tsang's writings as the two main
themes of the Three Treatises, the principal Indian
Madhyamaka texts in the eyes of the Chinese
Buddhists:(21)
However, although there are three treatises,
their purports are just two: first, revealing
truths, second, refuting falsehoods. By refuting
falsehoods, they rescue [sentient beings] sunk
[in sins] below; by revealing truths, they
promote the Great Dharma above. Hence, summing
up the essential points, [we obtain] just these
two [principles].(22)
However, just to say in general that the Madhyamaka
is concerned with "refuting falsehoods" and
"revealing truths" tells us little about the
peculiar character of Madhyamaka thought, for the
same can be said of the thought of all other
Buddhist schools, and, as a matter of fact, of the
thought of all non-Buddhist schools as well. What is
special about the Madhyamaka in this respect is its
singular way of conceiving the relation between the
two functions, a way arising from its conception of
the quintessence of truth as nonattachment:
The other `saastras refute [some ideas] and
establish [other ideas]. This is to aggravate
[the error of] acquisitiveness. Not only are
they incapable of expounding [truths], but they
are also incapable of refuting [falsehoods]....
These `saastras (the Four Treatises) only refute
and never establish. [As a result,] not only are
they capable of refuting [falsehoods], but they
are also capable of establishing [truths].(23)
While "refuting falsehoods" and "revealing
truths" are tasks common to all Buddhist schools,
whether Madhyamaka or non-Madhyamaka, the
non-Madhyamaka schools generally espouse some
special theories of Reality, such as the theory of
the real existence of dharmas in the case of the
Sarvaastivaadins, the theory of universal
nothingness in the case of the Satyasiddhi-`saastra,
the theory of ideation-only in the case of the
Yogaacaarins, and so forth.(24) Ideas and practices
in conflict with these theories are rejected by them
as definitely false, whereas ideas and practices in
agreement with these theories are embraced by them
as definitely true; and "refuting falsehoods" and
"revealing truths" appear as two distinct functions
in their teachings. The Madhyamaka, on the other
hand, admits nothing other than nonattachment to be
the truth, and nonattachment, as we have just
explained, is understood in the Madhya make as the
nongrasping of any form of idea and practice, up to
the very idea and practice of nonattachment.
Consequently, "revealing truths" in
P.653
the Madhyamaka consists not in establishing the
validity of certain doctrinal and behavioral
patterns, but rather in demonstrating the
untenability of any such attempt, that is, in
"refuting falsehoods"; and "refuting falsehoods" and
"revealing truths" are actually two sides of the
same coin in the Madhyamaka's case.
This explains why Chi-tsang would fault the
other schools for "aggravating the error of
acquisitiveness" and for "being incapable of
refuting falsehoods" in practicing "refuting
falsehoods" and "revealing truths" in separate. This
also explains why Chi-tsang, while proffering
"refutation of falsehoods" and "revelation of
truths" as the dual concerns of the Three Treatises,
would declare at the same time that the Madhyamaka
"only refutes and never establishes." In Chi-tsang's
opinion, just because the Three Treatises do not
establish any truth, they establish most perfectly
the truth of nonattachment.
C. The Two forms and Three forms of Truth. In thus
making nonattachment the sole criterion of truth,
Chi-tsang empties the concept of truth of any
determinate content. And if he still describes some
statements and beliefs to be true, he makes it
perfectly plain that his primary consideration is
their efficacy in refuting false views and
cultivating nonattachment. We can see this from his
analysis of truth into the two aspects of
"substance" (t'i) and "function" (yung):
[What is] neither "supreme" nor "mundane" is
called 'truth qua substance"; the "supreme" and
the "mundane" are designated "truths qua
function." It is so because the true character
of dharmas defies description and is beyond
thought, and is never [to be considered as]
"supreme" or "mundane." Hence, we call it
"substance." Since it transcends all [forms of]
one-sidedness and falsehood, we designate it
"truth." Hence, we speak of "truth qua
substance."
As for "truths qua function," since [the
"truth qua] substance" is beyond names and
speech, [ordinary] beings have no means of
realizing it. [Hence,] although [the holy man]
is without the thoughts of "being" and
"nonbeing," he talks tentatively of [the idea of
nonbeing as the] "supreme [truth]" and of [the
idea of being as the] "mundane [truth]." Thus,
we call [their ideas of "supreme" and "mundane"]
"function." [As] these [ideas of] "supreme" and
"mundane" are also not one-sided and false, we
designate them "truth." Thus, we call them
"truths qua function."(25)
The terms "supreme" and "mundane" in the passage
above refer to the "supreme truth" and the "mundane
truth," the former pertaining to the realm of the
enlightened and the latter pertaining to the realm
of the nonenlightened. We shall deal with
Chi-tsang's interpretation of these two forms of
truth in detail later. Meanwhile, for our present
purpose, it is significant to observe that Chi-tsang
maintains that the "truth qua substance," that is,
truth-in-itself, is neither supreme nor mundane,
that is, is not tied to any specific truth, be it of
the supramundane or of the mundane order.
p.654
Chi-tsang duly notes the need to resort
tentatively to the supreme and mundane truths in
order to reveal the "truth qua substance." For
instance, in order to make his followers give up the
belief in a permanent self, which he considered to
be the most serious impediment to the realization of
nonattachment, the Buddha disparaged this belief as
a notion of the mundane world, and lauded the
doctrine of five skandhas, which he put forward to
undermine the belief, as a case of supreme
truth.(26) In like manner, the
Praj~naapaaramitaa-suutras apply the epithet
"mundane" to the AAbhidharmika theory of the real
existence of self-sufficient dharmas and append the
description "supreme" to its own teaching of
emptiness.(27) Yet, it should always be borne in
mind that such judgments of "mundane" and "supreme"
derive their validity entirely from their
effectiveness as means to make known the "truth qua
substance"; that is, they are "truths qua function."
As such, they enjoy no independent status as truth
outside the function of eradicating false beliefs,
and should not be held onto irrespective of change
in circumstances.
Chi-tsang goes on to give another analysis of
truth into three forms:
But there are three forms of truth:
1. What is designated "truth" in contradistinction
to the error of one-sidedness. It is called "truth
in contradistinction to one-sidedness" (tui-p'ien
cheng).
2. What is called truth due to the complete
clearance of one-sidedness. It is referred to as
"truth qua complete [clearance] of one-sidedness"
(chin-p'ien cheng).
3. When the error of one-sidedness has been removed,
the truth also is not retained, and there is neither
one-sidedness nor truth. Not knowing how to laud
[this state], we tentatively extol it as true, and
refer to it as the "non-conditioned truth"
(chueh-tai cheng).(28)
The first form of truth, "truth in contradistinction
to one-sidedness," earns the title of "truth" for
its potency to eliminate the error of one-sidedness,
and is equivalent to "truth qua function." Its
successful application results in the "complete
clearance of one-sidedness," which is enumerated as
the second form of truth. Yet, if one grasps at the
complete clearance of one-sidedness as the truth,
that would also be a kind of one-sidedness Hence,
one has to get rid of the thought of the distinction
between one-sidedness and truth before the real
abolition of one-sidedness can be achieved. The
consummate state of nonattachment thus attained, in
which reliance on every category of thought and
action has disappeared, is presented as the third
form of truth and is given the name
"non-conditioned." It is equivalent to "truth qua
substance."
P.655
D. The Concept of "Truth as Nonattachment" as a
Hermeneutic Principle. Chi-tsang's highly
negativistic conception of truth and pragmatic view
of the truth of propositions are clearly reflected
in his opinion about the purpose of Buddhist
teachings and scriptures. Chi-tsang reports these
words of Fa-lang on the significance of Buddhist
teachings:
[My] teacher said: Whatever we say [should] all
be for the sake or stopping errors. When errors
are stopped, speech ceases. It is just like
hailstones which crush grass. When the grass is
dead, the hailstones disappear. We should not
adhere to words and form opinions. If we adhere
to words and form opinions, we shall fall into
errors once again and can not attain
deliverance.(29)
In the opinion of Fa-lang and Chi-tsang, Buddhist
ideas and theories are not formulated as eternal
truths depicting the constituents and essence of the
ultimate reality, but are invented as instruments to
check errors. Consequently, they should be abandoned
right away once they have fulfilled their intended
role. Chi-tsang is hotly hostile to any tendency to
divorce scriptural teachings from their original
function of refuting falsehoods and to treat
Buddhist doctrines as fixed dogmas. Commenting on
those Buddhists who, having missed the critical
intent of Naagaarjuna's system of eight negations,(30)
construct various positive theories based on their
surface meanings, Chi-tsang writes:
Such a person cannot be converted. It is so
because he who harbors fixed opinions on
investigating [the meanings of] the suutras
cannot be converted even by the Buddhas, and he
who forms the mind of attachment after studying
the `saastras cannot be converted even by the
Bodhisattvas. When a person cannot be converted,
whether by sutras or `saastras, both Buddhas and
Bodhisattvas, we know that his faculties are
dull and his sins are serious. To this person,
whether suutras or `saastras, both Buddhas and
Bodhisattvas, all are poisons.(31)
He who reifies the provisional remarks of the
Buddhas and Bodhisattvas and looks upon the sayings
of the suutras and `saastras as eternally valid
"cannot be converted, " for whatever advice is
addressed to him will be taken up by him forthwith
as another object to adhere to, and will become
another cause of attachment as a result. Thus, it is
asserted that "to this person, whether suutras or
`saastras, both Buddhas and Bodhisattvas, all are
poisons."
But if what are originally beneficial will turn
harmful when they are 'being approached in an
acquisitive frame of mind, what are judged harmful
by the common standard would become beneficial when
they contribute to the realization of the state of
nonattachment. Hence, after criticizing
miscellaneous theories about the central theme of
the Saddharmapu.n.dariika-suutra, Chi-tsang turns
around and observes:
P.656
Supposing [an explanation] agrees with the
suutras but hearing it does not lead to
awakening, it is not the [right] medicine for
its objects [of instruction] and should be
abandoned. [On the other hand, ] if an
explanation conflicts with the Buddhist suutras
and yet hearing it results in acceptance of the
[Buddhist] Way, it becomes [salutary like] sweet
dews and it is only right that it should be
recorded down. Hence, whether [an explanation
is] sweet or poisonous is not definite. Only
awakening is the essential principle.(32)
Chi-tsang considers the central theme of the
Saddharmapu.n.dariika-suutra and, as a matter of
fact, of all Buddhist suutras to be "awakening"
(wu), which means, in the concext of his teaching of
nonattachment, the liberation from all adherences to
and reliances on definite patterns of thought and
behavior. So long as an exposition of the scripture
serves this end, it should be adopted even if it
seems to go against the outward meaning of the text.
On the other hand, an explanation which appears to
be truthful to the text should be rejected, when its
promulgation produces the opposite effect. Chi-tsang
goes so far as to suggest that diverse
interpretations of the same scripture can all be
judged "not wrong" when they lead similarly to
awakening, and should all be deemed "not right" if
they give rise alike to delusion:
To sum up what has been said, there are
altogether three ways (of looking at these
diverse explanations]: first, if their objects
[of instruction] all achieve awakening [on
listening to them], then these various
explanations are not wrong. Second, if on
hearing them, [the objects of instruction] all
become deluded, then these diverse theories are
not right. Third, there may be occasions [when
an explanation is conducive to] awakening at one
place and produces delusion at another place.
Then, it is called "true" at one place and is
named "false" at another place.(33)
All in all, practical religious consideration
has superseded consistency and accuracy as the
guiding principle of Chi-tsang's hermeneutics.
Chi-tsang's Teaching of Two Truths
An examination of Chi-tsang's theory of truth
would not be complete without some discussion of his
interpretation of the important Buddhist concept of
"two truths," an interpretation so innovative that
it is commonly regarded as Chi-tsang's most
important achievement as a Buddhist thinker.(34)
A. Theories of Two Truths before Chi-tsang. The
Sanskrit original of the term "two truths, "
satyadvaya, suggests the existence of two levels of
Reality and their corresponding states of knowledge:
the first, pertaining to the common world of
everyday discourse, is named "mundane truth"
(sa.mv.rti-satya, su-ti, shih-ti) ; the second,
understandable only to the transcendental wisdom of
the enlightened, is called "supreme truth"
(paramaartha-satya, chen-ti, ti-i-i ti).(35) The
notion of two levels of Being
P.657
and knowledge, one inferior and one superior, was
already present in Early Buddhist writings.(36) It
later found its way into various Hiinayaana texts,
such as the Abhidharmamahaavibhaa.saa-`saastra and
the Abhidharmako`sa-`saastra,(37) and was touched
upon in such early Mahaayaana works as the
Praj~naapaaramitaa-suutras.(38) We find in early
Madhyamaka writings constant reference to the
concept. The best-known case by far is the
following, in chapter 24 of Naagaarjuna's famous
Muulamadhyamaka-kaarikaa:
The Buddhas have recourse to the two truths on
preaching the Dharma for sentient beings: first,
the mundane truth, second, the supreme truth.
If a person does not know how to distinguish
between the two truths,
He will not know the real meaning of the
profound Buddha Dharma.(39)
The Madhyamaka-`saastra, the earliest extant
exegesis on the Muulamadhyamaka-kaarikaa, comments
thus on these verses:
With respect to the "mundane truth," all dharmas
are in nature empty. Yet, [the opinion of] the
world is fallacious, and hence there arise false
dharmas which are [regarded as] real "from the
standpoint of the world" (yu shih-ch'ien). The
sages and the holy men truly know the fallacious
nature [of the opinions of the world], and hence
they know that all dharmas are empty and
nonoriginating. [This knowledge] is the "supreme
truth" [seen] "from the standpoint of the holy
men" (yu sheng-jen) and is called "real." The
Buddhas have recourse to these two truths on
preaching the Dharma for sentient beings. If a
person cannot correctly distinguish between the
two truths, then he will not know the real
meaning of the very profound Buddha Dharma.(40)
The "mundane truth" is truth by the standard of the
world. For example, ordinary people do not realize
that dharmas are conditioned in nature, and
erroneously look upon them as real. This view of the
real existence of dharmas is a "mundane truth." The
"supreme truth" is truth as known to the saints. For
example, recognizing the conventional belief of real
existence to be erroneous, the saints deem all
dharmas to be in essence empty and nonoriginating.
This view of the emptiness of dharmas is a "supreme
truth." According to the Muulamadhyamaka-kaarikaa
and Madhyamaka-`saastra, the distinction between
"mundane truth" and "supreme truth" is postulated by
the Buddhas in order to instruct sentient beings,
and we can never come to see the true meaning of the
Buddha Dharma without first comprehending its real
significance.
It is important to note that the Madhyamaka does
not dismiss the "mundane truth" offhandedly as
worthless, despite the intimation of its being the
truth of the worldly realm. This can be seen from
the next stanza of the Muulamadhyamaka-kaarikaa and
the Madhyamaka-`saastra's exposition of it:
P.658
Without having recourse to the two truths, the
supreme [truth] cannot be obtained.
Without obtaining the supreme [truth], nirvaa.na
can not be obtained.(41)
The supreme [truth] is [made known] entirely
through speech, and speech is [a kind of]
mundane [object]. Hence, [it is said that]
without having recourse to the mundane [truth],
the supreme [truth] cannot be taught. And
without obtaining the supreme [truth], how can
nirvaa.na be attained? Hence, although dharmas
are nonoriginating, there are [two forms of]
truth.(42)
Here, the Madhyamaka-`saastra goes further to
identify the "mundane truth" with speech, which is
generally considered in Buddhism as an outgrowth of
the worldly belief in the real existence of dharmas.
Now, although the "supreme truth, " being the
negation of the belief of real existence, has
basically nothing to do with speech, it cannot be
communicated to the noninitiated without the aid of
speech. Hence, it is said that without the "mundane
truth" (now understood as "speech"), people cannot
obtain the "supreme truth." And without obtaining
the "supreme truth," people naturally cannot realize
nirvaa.na.(43)
The translation of the Madhyamaka-`saastra, as
well as of the Davaada`samukha-`saastra, the
`Sata-`saastra, and the
Mahaapraj~naapaaramitaa-`saastra, into Chinese by
Kumaarajiiva in the first decade of the fifth
century marked the beginning of the Chinese
Madhyamaka movement. Since most of the
aforementioned texts contain remarks about the two
truths,(44) it was not surprising that the attention
of Kumaarajiiva's followers would become drawn to
the concept. Both Seng-tao and Chu Tao-sheng (ca.
360-434) had written special treatises on the two
truths,(45) and T'an-ying and Seng-chao (374-414)
cited the terms "supreme truth" and "mundane truth"
a number of times in their Writings.(46) While the
influence of Madhyamaka texts was on the wane by the
mid-fifth century with the ascendancy of the
Satyasiddhi-`saastra and the Mahaayaana
Mahaaparinirvaa.na-suutra, the interest of Chinese
Buddhists in the two truths did not subside, since
discussions about the two truths also figure
prominently in these two newly revered
scriptures.(47)
By the early sixth century, the "two truths" had
established itself as a cardinal Buddhist theme in
the minds of most Chinese Buddhist thinkers A
considerable amount of information about the various
interpretations of the two truths in circulation at
that time, mostly of a piecemeal, secondary nature,
has been passed down to us, from which we learn that
the idea had been analyzed from a variety of
perspectives and had been correlated with other
currently popular Buddhist ideas, such as the
"misddle path, " "Buddha-nature," and so forth.
However, since most of the presently known exponents
of the idea of two truths of that period had left
behind no comprehensive, systematic philosophical
writing,it is impossible for us today to place their
fragmentary observations about the
P.659
two truths in the context of their overall teachings
in order to apprehend their precise import. On the
whole, it is safe to assume that with respect to the
two main Chinese Buddhist doctrinal traditions of
the sixth century, commonly referred to as the
Ch'eng-shih School and Ti-lun School, the former,
basing its teaching upon the Satyasiddhi-`saastra
(Ch'eng-shih lun) , took over the `Saastra's
interpretation, considering the notion of the real
existence of everyday objects and dharmas to be the
"mundane truth," and regarding the knowledge of the
nonexistence of all forms of beings to be the
"supreme truth."(48) As for the latter, we shall
take the opinion of Ching-ying Hui-yuan (523-592), a
leading Ti-lun master of Chi-tsang's time, as
representative.
In his monumental work, the Ta-cheng I-chang,
Hui-yuan devotes a special section to the topic of
the two truths, where he considers the relation
between the "mundane truth" and the "supreme truth"
from the two aspects of "dependence" (i-ch'ih) and
"origination" (yuan-ch'i):
When the two [truths] are explained from [the
perspective of] "dependence, " the false
phenomena are taken as the dependent [objects]
and the true [consciousness] is [considered as
the subject] being depended on. The false
phenomena which are dependent are said to be the
"mundane truth''; the true [consciousness] being
depended on is classified as the "supreme
truth." When the two [truths] are explained from
[the perspective of] "origination," the pure
Dharmadhaatu, [that is,] the tathaagatagarbha,
[engages in the activities of] origination and
gives birth to [the realms of] sa.msaara and
nirvaa.na. The true nature [of the
tathaagatagarbha] itself is said to be the
"supreme truth"; the function of "origination"
is classified as the "mundane truth."(49)
In this passage, the "supreme truth" is equated with
the true consciousness, which constitutes the
ontological ground of both sa.msaaric and nirvaa.nic
existence in the Ti-lun picture of Reality; and the
"mundane truth" is identified with false phenomena
which arise from the true consciousness, also known
as the tathaagatagarbha, when the latter comes under
the influence of ignorance. The aspect "origination"
indicates that the false phenomenal order originates
from the true consciousness; the aspect "dependence"
indicates that the false phenomenal order is
sustained by the true consciousness. All in all, in
the Ta-cheng I-chang, the concept of "two truths"
has been assimilated into the Ti-lun metaphysical
framework, and is used to illustrate the teaching of
consciousness-only 'espoused by the School.(50)
B. The Two Truths qua Instruction (Chiao-ti). The
preceding sketch of the early Chinese
interpretations of the "two truths" has shown that
there existed a general tendency to associate the
"supreme truth'' and the "mundane truth" with two
ontological levels of Reality, one actual and the
other illusory. Chi-tsang devotes a large part of
his exposition of the two truths to demonstrating
the untenability of this approach. Quoting
P.660
Naagaarjuna's statement that "the Buddhas have
recourse to the two truths on preaching the Dharma
for sentient beings, " he asserts that the
distinction between "supreme truth" and "mundane
truth" is postulated by the Buddhas as a "means of
instruction," and that the two truths do not stand
for two objective "realms" and "principles":
[Naagaarjuna] explains that the Tathaagatas
always have recourse to the two truths on
preaching the Dharma: first, the mundane truth,
second, the supreme truth. Hence, the two truths
are just means of instruction and are not
concerned with objects and principles.(51)
To take the two truths as indicating two separate
realms and principles is an instance of dualistic
thinking; and dualistic thinking is synonymous with
attachment in Madhyamaka thought. Being a
Maadhyamika and strongly opposed to attachment of
any form, Chi-tsang naturally deems it impossible
that the Buddhas would conceive the two truths as
referring to two separate realms and principles:
Further, if [we take] the two truths as two
principles, that would constitute
"acquisitiveness."... Sentient beings already
have the error of [harboring] dualistic views.
If the Buddhas further teach that the true
principle is dual, then not only is their old
error not got rid of, but new delusions would
also be added. For this reason, the Buddhas,
[with a view to] adapting to [the understanding
of] sentient beings, say that there are two
truths. Actually, the true principle is not
dual.(52)
Pivotal to Chi-tsang's teaching of the two
truths is the concept of "two truths qua
instruction," which is defined as follows:
By [the two truths qua] "instruction" [we mean
that] the true [principle] is originally
nondual, and it is for the sake of the objects
[of instruction] that it is spoken of as dual.
Hence, [the two truths] are called
"instruction."(53)
Given the centrality of the precept of nonattachment
in Chi-tsang's teaching, the "true principle"
mentioned here should be none other than the
principle of nonattachment. As nonattachment is the
abolition of all thoughts of duality, it is said
that "the true principle is originally nondual."
However, sentient beings cling to all sorts of
beliefs, and to make them abandon their clingings,
the Buddhas disparage the beliefs they cherish as
"mundane" and extol the opposite beliefs as
"supreme." Hence, it is said that "it is for the
sake of the objects of instruction that the true
principle is spoken of as dual." In Chi-tsang's
opinion, the duality of "mundane" and "supreme" is
invented by the Buddhas purely as a pedagogical
device to uproot attachments, and does not reflect
the Buddha's true state of knowledge, which is
absolutely nondiscriminating. This opinion is
reflected in Chi-tsang's rejection or the popular
understanding of the "mundane" as "void and
fleeting" and of the "supreme"
P.661
as "real and solid." It is also implied in the
following remarks, which assert that "mundane" has
"nonmundane" and "supreme" has "nonsupreme" as
meaning:'"
The two truths are also like that. As "supreme"
signifies "nonsupreme" and "mundane" signifies
"nonmundane, " "supreme'" and "mundane" are
provisional expressions. Being provisional
expressions, [the two] terms do not have the
effect of acquiring things, and things do not
have the substances corresponding to [the two]
terms.(55)
According to Chi-tsang, only when one gives up the
idea that the terms "supreme" and "mundane" indicate
specific "supreme" and "mundane" objects will one
truly come to comprehend the real significance of
the Buddhas' usage of the terms "supreme" and
"mundane."
C. The Two Truths qua Standpoints (Yu-ti). If
"supreme truth" and "mundane truth" do not denote
two distinct levels of Reality, the question then
arises as to why the Madhyamaka-`saastra cites the
popular belief in the real existence of dharmas as a
case of "mundane truth" and gives the holy man's
perception of the emptiness of dharmas as an
instance of "supreme truth." Are "real existence"
and "emptiness" not two levels 'of Reality? Are
their cognitions not two levels of knowledge?
Chi-tsang answers these queries by postulating
another form of "two truths," the "two truths qua
standpoints." The concept "two truths qua
standpoints" is derived from the
Madhyamaka-`saastra, which, as we have seen, says
that everyday objects are considered as real "from
the standpoint of the world" but are recognized as
empty "from the standpoint of the holy man":(56)
The `Saastra itself explains: dharmas are empty
in nature. [Yet, the opinion of] the world is
fallacious, and maintains that they are
existent. From the standpoint of the people of
the world, [the view of existence] is true to
the fact and is called a "truth." The sages and
holy men truly know the fallacious nature [of
worldly opinions] and the empty nature [of
dharmas]. From the standpoint of the holy men,
[the view of emptiness] is true to the fact and
is called a "truth." These [views of "existence"
and "emptiness"] are the "two truths qua
standpoints." What the Buddhas preach having
recourse to these [views] are called the "[two]
truths qua instruction."(57)
As Chi-tsang sees it, when the Madhyamaka-`saastra
puts forward the idea of real existence as the
"mundane truth" and the idea of emptiness as the
"supreme truth, " it is relating two opposite
"standpoints" concerning the nature of Reality,
standpoints which the Buddhas bring up on preaching
the Dharma without actually endorsing either of
them. Thus, in order to counteract the everyday
man's realistic standpoint, the Buddhas have
recourse to the contrary standpoint of emptiness,
disparaging the former as "worldly" and "mundane,"
and praising the latter as "holy" and "supreme."
P.662
However, it should be remembered that the
standpoint of emptiness is brought in by the Buddhas
solely as an antidote to the standpoint of real
existence. When the Buddhas picture "real existence"
as a "mundane" concept and "emptiness" as a
"supreme" concept, they are not asking their
audiences to exchange "real existence" for
"emptiness" as the true ontological idea. When the
role of "truths qua standpoints" to eliminate
attachment to every standpoint is properly
comprehended, it would be perceived that the "truths
qua standpoints" actually function in the Buddhas'
teaching as "truths gua instruction."
The term "two truths qua standpoints" is coined
for the sake of sentient beings. it is for the
sake of sentient beings that [the Buddhas] say
that [the view of] "existence" [represents] the
standpoint of the ordinary [people and] is the
mundane truth; it is for the sake of sentient
beings that [the Buddhas] say that [the view of]
"emptiness" [represents] the standpoint of the
holy men [and] is the supreme truth. Since it is
for the sake of sentient beings that [the
Buddhas] talk about "emptiness" and "existence,"
which are the "two truths qua standpoints," the
"two truths' qua standpoints" are also "[truths
qua] instruction."(58)
Judging from the fact that "existence" and
"emptiness" are two conflicting opinions about the
nature of Reality, they are "truths qua
standpoints." Judging from the fact that "existence"
and "emptiness" are propounded by the Buddhas for
the sake of guiding sentient beings and not for the
sake of establishing a specific metaphysical
position, they are "truths qua instruction." To
perceive that "truths qua standpoints" serve in the
teaching of the Buddhas mainly as tentative devices
to negate standpoints is highly important, for
failing to do so has resulted in the erroneous
identification of some metaphysical standpoints as
the Buddhas' standpoints. It is in order to guard
against misunderstanding of this sort that Chi-tsang
differentiates between two types of "truth qua
standpoints": "truths qua standpoints [the Buddhas]
have recourse to" (so-i yu-ti) and "truths qua
standpoints missing the heuristic [intent] (mi-chiao
yu-ti) [of the Buddhas]":(59)
If it is so, then there are two forms of "truths
qua standpoints": first, "truths qua standpoints
[the Buddhas] have recourse to," second, "truths
qua standpoints missing the heuristic
[intent]."... The "truths qua standpoints [the
Buddhas] have recourse to" are "original"; the
"truths qua standpoints missing the heuristic
[intent]" are "derivative."
The "truths qua standpoints [the Buddhas]
have recourse to" being original, let us discuss
this by referring to `Saakyamuni's life work.
Before the appearance of Saakyamuni, there were
already these "two truths qua standpoint s."
`Saakyamuni had recourse to these two truths on
preaching the Dharma for sentient beings. For
what reason? [It is because] all Buddhas without
exception preach the Dharma by having recourse
to the two truths. Hence, [`Saakyamuni] had
recourse to the two truths from the very start
on preaching [the Dharma.
P.663
Thus,] it should be known that the "truths qua
standpoints [the Buddhas] have recourse to" are
"original."
The "truths qua standpoints missing the
heuristic [intent]" are derivative because they
are "[truths qua] standpoins" formed when
sentient beings entertain the opinions of
"existence" and "nonexistence" after receiving
the Tathaagata's teaching of the two truths of
"existence" and "nonexistence." These ["truths
qua standpoints"] come later [and so are known
as "derivative"].(60)
According to Chi-tsang, the two ideas of
"existence" and "emptiness" were already a part of
the popular conceptual apparatus before
`Saakyamuni's appearance in the world,(61) and they
were adopted by `Saakyamuni as expedient teaching
devices from the very beginning of his preaching
career. So they are called "truths qua standpoints
the Buddhas have recourse to," Those practitioners
of dull faculties could not discern the
soteriological intent behind `Saakyamuni's
discourses on "existence" and "emptiness, " and
regarded `Saakyamuni's references to the former
notion as "mundane" and to the latter notion as
"supreme" as judgments about ontological primacy.
They mistook provisional ideas for definite
opinions, and so their definite opinions of
"existence" and "emptiness" are called "truths qua
standpoints missing the heuristic intent of the
Buddhas."
Since the "truths qua standpoints the Buddhas
have recourse to" inaugurated `Saakyamuni's mission
of universal salvation, they are said to be
"original." Since the "truths qua standpoints
missing the heuristic intent" came about due to the
misconceiving of the real purpose of the "truths qua
standpoints the Buddhas have recourse to," they are
said to be "derivative." Chi-tsang goes further to
distinguish "three alternatives" (san-chu) in
connection with the correct comprehension and the
incorrect comprehension of the "two truths qua
standpoints":
There are three alternative [judgments] with
respect to the "[two] truths qua standpoints":
first, they are both correct, second, they are
both incorrect, third, they are [one] correct
and [one] incorrect.
[1] [The two truths qua standpoints are one]
correct and [one] incorrect: from the standpoint
of the ordinary [people, things] are existent.
This [view of] existence is incorrect. The sages
and the holy men truly know that [things are] in
nature empty. This [view of] emptiness is
correct.
[2] The two [truths qua standpoints] are both
incorrect: since the two [views of "existence"
and "emptiness"] are both standpoints, both are
incorrect.
[3] The two [truths qua standpoints] are both
correct: on knowing the two standpoints [of
"existence" and "emptiness"], one knows right
away [the truth of] "nonduality." Seeing neither
"duality" nor "nonduality," one transcends all
the five alternatives.(62)
P.664
Now, of these alternatives, the first two
alternatives are equivalent to "truths qua
standpoints," while the last alternative is
equivalent to "truth pua instruction."(63)
The alternative of "one correct and one
incorrect" is exemplified by the initial propagation
of the two truths by `Saakyamuni, when the
standpoint of existence was dismissed as "mundane"
and "incorrect" and the opposite standpoint of
emptiness was proffered as "supreme" and "correct."
It is the same as the "truth qua standpoint the
Buddhas have recourse to." The alternative of "both
incorrect" points to the fallacious interpretation
of `Saakyamuni's reference to the standpoint of
existence as "correct" and to the standpoint of
emptiness as "incorrect" as an injunction to discard
one ontological standpoint in favor of another
ontological standpoint. It is none other than the
"truths qua standpoints missing the heuristic intent
of the Buddhas." Lastly, the alternative of "both
correct" is the correct knowledge of `Saakyamuni's
method of making use of one standpoint to undermine
another standpoint, the final goal being the
transcending of all specific standpoints, that is,
the realization of the truth of nonduality. It
rightly recognizes the role which the standpoints of
existence and emptiness play in `Saakyamuni's
teaching, that is, as "truth qua instruction."
D. The Three forms and Four Forms of Two Truths. The
foregoing discussion of the "two truths qua
instruction" and the "two truths qua standpoints"
underscores Chi-tsang's pragmatic view of truth. To
be sure, pragmatism had already played a significant
part in discussions of the two truths before
Chi-tsang, in the form of affirming the necessity of
resorting to the mundane truths in order to reveal
the supreme truth. But pragmatism had seldom been
extended to the reading of the very distinction
between mundane truth and supreme truth. White the
remark of the Muulamadhyamaka-kaarikaa that "the
Buddhas have recourse to the two truths on preaching
the Dharma for sentient beings" does suggest that
the duality of "mundane truth" and "supreme truth"
is adopted by the Buddhas to cater to the needs of
ordinary sentient beings, this meaning is hinted at
and is not directly expressed. The same is true of
the reference to the duality of "existence" and
"emptiness" to throw light upon. the relation
between the two truths in the Madhyamaka-`saastra.
Chi-tsang's ability to make explicit the implicit,
thereby turning the theory of two truths into a
powerful illustration of his conception of truth as
nonattachment, bespeaks keen intellectual acumen.
In conclusion, we shall take a brief look at
Chi-tsang's schemes of three forms and of four forms
of two truths. They are good illustrations of
Chi-tsang's idea of two truths as means of
instruction. The three forms of two truths are:
P.665
The first [form of two truths] takes "existence"
as the mundane truth and "emptiness" as the
supreme truth. The next [form of two truths]
takes "existence" and "emptiness" as both
mundane [truths] and [considers] "neither
existence nor emptiness" as the supreme [truth].
The third [form of two truths] takes the
"duality" and the "nonduality" [of existence and
emptiness] as mundane [truths] and [considers]
"neither duality nor nonduality" as the supreme
[truth].(64)
The passage above can be summed up in a table (Table 1).
Chi-tsang gives the following explanation of how
teaching the three forms of two truths helps to free
the minds of sentient beings from clinging to
determinate ideas:
From the beginningless past, [sentient beings]
cherish their bodily forms, their minds,
external objects, and so forth, and maintain
that they are real. Hence, the Buddhas appear in
the world and preach for them as follows: "These
[things] are real [at the level of] the mundane
[truth] only, and are not real [in the eyes of]
the holy [man]. lust [the knowledge that] all
dharmas are empty in their original nature is
called the supreme truth...." Then sentient
beings maintain that "existence" is not the real
[truth] and that "emptiness" is the real
[truth]. They abandon [the idea of] "existence"
[only] to grasp at [the idea of] "emptiness."
Hence, [the Buddhas go on to] tell them,
"Regarding `emptiness' and 'existence,' these
are two extremes and are both mundane truths.
[Only the idea of] 'neither emptiness nor
existence,' [that is] the truth of the middle
way, is the supreme truth."
Although the deluded ones [on hearing the
second form of two truths] abandon the two
extreme [ideas of "existence" and "emptiness"],
they in turn get bogged down in [the idea of]
the "middle way." Hence, [the Buddhas address
them] the third time land] explain that not to
become attached to the "middle way" after
leaving far behind the two extremes [of
"existence" and "emptiness"] is the supreme
truth, and that the two extremes and the "middle
way" are all mundane truths.(65)
Seeing that sentient beings cherish their bodily
forms, their minds, and the objects of the external
world, the Buddhas teach the first form of
Table 1. The Three Forms of Two Truths
-----------------------------------------------------------
Form Mundane Truth Supreme Truth
-----------------------------------------------------------
1 Existence Emptiness
2 Duality of "existence" and "emptiness" Nonduality of
"existence" and
"emptiness"
(neither "existence"
nor "emptiness")
3 Duality of "duality" and "nonduality" Neither "duality"
nor "nonduality"
------------------------------------------------------------
P.666
two truths, upholding "emptiness" as the supreme
truth in order to refute the mundane belief in real
"existence." On hearing the Buddhas' words, those
sentient beings of sharp faculties see right away
the Buddhas' real objective to cultivate
nonattachment, and would give up the standpoint of
"existence" without retaining the standpoint of
"emptiness." The majority of listeners, however,
being of dull intelligence, are prompted by their
ingrained habit of discriminative thinking to
consider the ideas of "existence" and "emptiness" as
two opposite ontological standpoints, the former to
be discarded and the latter to be accepted. They
abandon the standpoint of "existence," only to grasp
at the standpoint of "emptiness.'' Noticing this,
the Buddhas go on to bring in the second form of two
truths, pointing out that their dualistic conception
of "existence" and "emptiness" is still a case of
mundane truth, and that the supreme truth is the
foregoing of the standpoint of "emptiness" as well
a; the standpoint of "existence" ("neither being nor
emptiness").
Yet, the listeners' proclivity for grasping at
standpoints persists. Although they forsake the
"duality" of existence and emptiness following the
instruction of the second form of two truths, they
take up the "nonduality" of existence and emptiness
as the standpoint to be endorsed. Consequently, the
Buddhas preach the third form of two truths, which
tells that to oppose "nonduality" to "duality" is
itself a form of dualistic thinking pertaining to
the realm of mundane truth, and that only the
abolition of the duality of "duality" and
"nonduality" ("neither duality nor nonduality") is
the true nonduality characteristic of the supreme
truth. Theoretically, this negative dialectic of
successive cancellation and production of
contradictions could go on ad infinitum;(66)
practically it would stop once the roots of
attachment of the listeners have been eradicated.
The scheme of four forms of two truths brings
into focus the heuristic function of the teaching of
three forms of two truths by introducing an
additional form of two truths, in which the three
forms of two truths are bracketed together as
"mundane":
[1] They (the Ch'eng-shih masters) merely take
"existence" as the mundane truth and "emptiness"
as the supreme truth.
[2] Now, we explain that "existence" and
"emptiness" are both mundane truths and only
"neither emptiness nor existence" is the supreme
truth.
[3] "Emptiness" and "existence" are a [form of]
duality; "neither emptiness nor existence" is a
[form of] nonduality. "Duality" and "nonduality"
are both mundane truths; "neither duality not
nonduality" is called the supreme truth. [4]
These three forms of two truths are all means of
instruction. We speak about these three
categories [of two truths] in order to make
[people] realize [the] non[difference of the]
three [categories of two truths]. Only
nondependence and nonacquisitiveness are called
[the true] principles.
P.667
Table 2. The Four Forms of Two Truths
------------------------------------------------------------------
Form Mundane Truth Supreme Truth
---------------------------------------------------------------- --
1 Existence Emptiness
2 Duality of "existence" and "emptiness" nonduality of
"existence" and
"emptiness"
3 Duality of "duality" and "nonduality" Neither "duality"
nor "nonduaiity"
4 The three forms of two truths Nondiffernece of
the three forms of
two truths
-------------------------------------------------------------------
QUESTION: [Do you mean that] the first three
[forms of two truths] are all mundane truths and
the non [difference of the] three [forms of two
truths] is the supreme truth?
REPLY: It is so.(67)
The thesis of each of the four forms of two
truths is illustrated in Table 2. Comparing Table 2
with Table 1, we can see right away that the first
three of the four forms of two truths correspond to
the three forms of two truths. The adding of the
fourth form makes it clear that the three forms of
two truths are "all means of instruction," that is,
they are distinctions invented for the purpose of
eliminating distinctions. Hence, they belong to the
group of mundane truths to be transcended. The
supreme truth is the "nondifference of the three
forms of two truths," that is, it is the true
principle of nonattachment which rises above all
distinctions, including the distinction between
three forms of two truths.
NOTES
This essay is a part of an ongoing research on the
development of Madhyamaka thought in China. I would
like to take this opportunity to thank Professor
Kenneth K. S. Ch'en for kindly agreeing to read over
my research manuscript and offering many insightful
comments. I am indebted to the Hsu Long-sing
Research Fund administered by the University of Hong
Kong for a grant which defrayed part of,the cost of
producing this manuscript.
1 - On Chi-tsang's life and contribution to the
Chinese Madhyamaka movement, consult Tao-hsuan
(596-667), Hsu Kao-seng chuan, T 50.513c-515a,
and Hirai Shunei, Chuugoku hannya shisohi
kenkyuu (Tokyo, 176), pp. 60-79, 345-352.
P.668
2 - Fa-lang's biography, in Tao-hsuan, Hsu Kao-seng
chuan, T 50.477b-478a.
3 - Sheng-man-ching Pao-k'u, T37.5c8-12.
4 - Ching-maing hsuan-lun, T38.888b21; and Fa-hua
i-su, T34.580c1-12.
5 - The "six ways" are the six forms of rebirth as
beings of hell, hungry ghosts, animals, asuras,
human beings, and gods.
6- "K'ai-shih" ("enlightened masters") is an epithet
used in praise of Bodhisattvas and learned
monks. The idea of "ssu-i" comes from the
Mahayana Mahaaparinirvaa.na-suutra, in which we
find mentioned "four" (ssu) categories of sages,
from those who have just left the world up to
the arhat, on whom sentient beings can rely (i)
to give comfort and protection. See T 12.396c.
In Chi-tsang's writings, the term "ssu-i
k'ai-shih" usually refers to Naagaarjuna. See,
for example, Chung-kuan-lun su, T 42.1c.
7 - San-lun hsuan-i, T45.7a23-26.
8 - Fa-hua yu-i, T34.644a1-2; and Fa-hua i-su,
T34,483b24.
9 - Chung-kuan-lun su, T34.418b1-2.
10 - Fa-hua hsuan-lun, T34.418b1-2.
11 - The Buddha frequently mentioned "desire" on
discussing the cause of suffering:
Whatsoever III arising has come upon me in the
past,--all that is rooted in desire, is joined
to desire. Whatsoever III arising may come upon
me in future time-all that is rooted in desire
is joined to desire. Desire is the root of III.
(Caroline A. F. Rhys Davids and Frank L.
Woodward, trans., The Book of the Kindred
Sayings [Samyutta-nikaaya], 5 vols. [London:
Pali Text Society, 1917-1930], vol. 4, p. 233)
12 - The Buddha traced the origin of desire to the
identification of one's self with the five
skandhas (body, feeling, perception,
activities, and consciousness), which are the
five main aspects of sentient existence:
And how, brethren, is there grasping and worry?
Herein, brethren, the untaught
many-folk,...--these regard body as the self,
the self as having body, body as being in the
self, the self as being in the body. Of such a
one the body alters and becomes otherwise.
Owing to the altering and the otherwiseness of
the body, his consciousness is busied with the
altering body. From this being busied with the
altering body, worried thoughts arise and
persist, laying hold of the heart. From the
laying hold of the heart he becomes troubled,
and owing to vexation and clinging he is
worried. He regards feeling as the self, the
self as having feeling, feeling as being the
self, the self as being in feeling. Of such a
one feeling alters and becomes otherwise...with
the same result. So also with perception... the
activities... the consciousness. Thus,
brethren, comes grasping and worry. (Ibid.,
vol. 3, pp. 16-17)
P.669
13 - The A.s.tasaahasrikaapraaj~naaparamitaa-suutra
mentions among the objects to be abandoned not
only the Hiinayaana fruits of Arhatship and
Pratyekabuddhahood, but also the Mahaayaana
fruit of Buddhahood:
I will teach you how a Bodhisattva should stand
in perfect wisdom. Through standing in
emptiness should he stand in perfect wisdom.
Armed with the great armour, the Bodhisattva
should so develop that he does not take his
stand on any of these: not on form, feeling,
perception, impulses, consciousness; not on
eye, ear, nose, tongue, body, mind;...not on
Pratyekabuddhahood, not on Buddhahood. (Edward
Conze, trans., The Perfection of Wisdom in
Eight;Thousand Lines & its Verse Summary, 2nd
rev. ed. [Bolinas, California: Four Seasons
Foundation, 1975], p. 97) The
Muulamadhyamaka-kaarikaa teaches the
nondifference of sa.msaara and nirvaa.na:
There is nothing whatever which
differentiates sa.msaara from nirvaa.na. And
there is also nothing whatever which
differentiates nirvaa.na from sa.msaara.
The extreme limit of nirvana is also the
extreme limit of sa.msaara;
There is not the slightest bit of difference
between these two limits.
(T 30.36a4-11)
14 - Fa-hua hsuan-lun, T34.391b16-20.
15 - Ching-ming hsuan-lun, T38.874b15-20.
16- Fa-hua i-su, T34.487c19.
17 - Nieh-p'an-ching yu-i, T38.232c17-19.
18 - Pai-lun su, T.42.239a22.
19 - San-lun hsuan-i, T45.6c12-16.
20 - Ta-ch'eng hsuan-lun, T45.68c19-21.
21 - The "three treatises" are the
Madhyamaka-`saastra (verse by Naagaarjuna,
commentary by Ch'ing-mu) , the
Dvaada`samukha-`saastra (attributed to
Naagaarjuna), and the `Saata-`saastra (verse by
AAryadeva, commentary by Bodhisattva Vasu).
22 - San-lun hsuan-i, T45.1a13-15.
23 - Ta-ch'eng hsuan-lun, T45.70a3-6.
24 - The teachings of the Sarvaativaadins, the
Satyasiddhi-`saastra, and the Yogaacaarins were
very popular in China in the sixth century, and
were constantly mentioned and criticized in
Chi-tsang's writings. Central to the
Sarvaastivaada picture of reality is the system
of seventy-five dharmas made out to be the most
basic elements of existence. The
Satyasiddhi-`saastra subjects the dharmas to
further analysis, and contends that the final
reality is the total emptiness arrived at
through continuous division. The Yogaacaara
postulates the existence of a
P.670
basic consciousness in every sentient being,
and considers all object of experience to be
formed from the ideas produced by this
consciousness.
25 - San-lun hsuan-i, T45.7b9-15.
26 - Refer to note 12 above for information about
the early Buddhist doctrines of "five skandhas"
and "nonself."
27 - Regarding the Hiinayaana belief of the real
existence of dharmas, see note 24 above. To
counter this belief, the
Praj~naapaaramitaa-suutras teach the emptiness
of all forms of existence. Hence, the
A.s.tasaahasrikaapraj~naapaaramitaa-suutra
asserts that all objective facts, all classes
of saints, and even nirvaa.na, are "like a
magical illusion, like a dream":
Like a magical illusion are these beings, like
a dream.... All objective facts also are like a
magical illusion, like a dream. The various
classes of saints, from Streamwinner to
Buddhahood, also are like a magical illusion,
like a dream.... Even Nirvaa.na, I say, is like
a magical illusion, is like a dream. How much
more so anything else! (Edward Conze, trans.,
The Perfection of Wisdom in Eight Thousand
Lines & its Verse Summary, pp. 98-99)
28 - San-lun hsuan-i, T 45.7b23-27.
29 - Chung-kuan-lun su, T42.27b13-16.
30 - The eight negations are negations of four pairs
of concepts, namely, origination and
extinction, permanence and annihilation,
identity and difference, and coming and going.
31 - Chung-kuan-lun su, T42.31c26-32a2.
32 - Fa-hua hsuan-lun, T34.381a15-17.
33 - Ibid., T34.381b16-19.
34 - On Chi-tsang's teaching of two truths, consult
Aaron K. Koseki, "Chi-tsang's
Ta-cheng-hsuan-lun: The Two Truths and the
Buddhanature" (Ph.D. diss., University of
Wisconsin-Madison, 1977), pp. 14-185; Hsueh-li
Cheng, "Zen and San-lun Maadhyamika Thought:
Exploring the Theoretical Foundation of Zen
Teachings and Practices," Religious Studies 15
(1979) : 346-351; Tokiwa Diajo, Zoku Shins
Bukkyo no kenkyuu (Tokyo, 1941), pp. 337-49;
Hirai Shunei, Chuugoku hannya shisoshi kenkyuu,
pp. 457-477, 561-592; Muranaka Yuusho, "Kajo
Daishi no o-kyo nitai ni tsuite," Indogaku
Bukkyogaku kenkyuu 8, no. 1 (1960): 160-161;
Sato Seijun; "Kichizo no shijuu nitai setsu,"
Sanko Bunka Kenkyuujo nempo 8 (1976): 155-180;
and Mitsugiri Jikai, "Kichizo no nitai-gi,"
Otani gakuho 60, no. 4 (1980): 1-10.
35 - See Mervyn Sprung,"The Madhyamaka Doctrine of
Two Realities as a Metaphysic," in Mervyn
Sprung, ed., The Problem of Two Truths in
Buddhism and Vedanta (Dordrecht,
Holland/Boston, Massachusetts: D. Reidel,
1973), p. 40.
P.671
36 - On the inception of the idea of two levels of
truth in Buddhism, consult Kulatissa N.
Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge
(London: George Alien & Unwin, 1963), pp.
361-368; Steven Collins, Selfless Persons
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982),
pp. 153-156; and Yasui Kosai, Chuugan shiso no
kenkyo (Kyoto, 1961), pp. 43-49.
37 - Abhidharmamahaavibhaa.saa-`saastra, T27.399c-400b,
and Abhidharma- ko`sa-`saastra, T 29.116b.
38 - See, for example, the
Pa~ncavi.m`satisaahasrika.
38 - See, forapaaramitaa-suutra, T8.378c, 397b-c and
405a.
39 - T 30.32c16-19.
40 - T 30.23c20-25.
41- T30.33a2-3.
42 - T 30.33a4-7.
43 - The Madhyamaka theory of two truths is
discussed in most works on Madhyamaka thought,
and is also the subject of numerous special
studies. See, for instance, the papers by
T.R.V. Murti, Frederick J. Streng, Mervyn
Sprung, and Bimal K. Matilal, in Mervyn Sprung,
ed., The Problem of the Two Truths in Buddhism
and Vedanta.
44 - For references to the two truths in the
`Sata-`saastra, see T 30.165a, 181c-182a. The
key passages on the two truths in the
Mahaapraj~naapaaramitaa-`saastra are listed in
Tamiki Koshiro, Chuugoku Bukkyo shiso no keisei
(Tokyo, 1971), pp. 462-467, and are discussed
in Paul L. Swanson, "The Two Truths Controversy
in China and Chih-i's Threefold Truth Concept"
(Ph.D. diss., University of Wisconsin-Madison,
1985), chap. 2, sec. 2.
45 -Among Chu Tao-sheng's writings mentioned in Chu
Tao-sheng's biography in Hui-chiao's (497-554)
Kao-seng chuan is one titled the Erh-ti lun
("On the two truths"), T50.366c18. The Kao-seng
chuan also mentions that Seng-tao was the
author of a treatise called the K'ung-yu erh-ti
lun ("On the two truths of emptiness and
being"), T 50.371b2.
46 - T'an-ying's preface to the Madhyamaka-`saastra
contains the earliest Chinese reference to the
terms "mundane truth" and "supreme truth" (T
55.77b1-6) . Seng-chao's writings also make
reference to these two terms. See T
45.154a5-26. Contemporary scholars have
stressed the contribution of these sources to
the formation of Chi-tsang's idea of "two
truths qua instruction." Consult Hirai Shunei,
"Kichizo Nitaisho no shiso to kozo," Komazawa
Daigaku Bukkyogakubu kenkyuu kiyo 27 (1969):
60-62; Chuugoku hannya shisoshi kenkyuu,
P.672
pp. 462-466; and Ikeda Shuujo, "Sojo no shuui
no hannyagaku shoshi no shiso ni kanshite,"
Taisho Daigaku Sogo Bukkyo Kenkyuujo nempo 7
(1985): 34-36.
47 - See, for instance, the Mahaayaana
Mahaaparinirvaa.na-suutra, T 12.443a-b, 465b-c,
603c; and Satyasiddhi-`saastra, T 32.316c-317a,
327a-c, 333a-b.
48 - So the Satyasiddhi-`saastra observes:
The annihilation of the marks of the five
skandhas is called the supreme truth. (T
32.316c25)
The five skandhas are really inexistent, and
are [only deemed to be] existent from [the
aspect of] the mundane truth. (T 32.333a8)
It should be known that [at the level of]
"supreme truth," beings are ail [considered to
be] inexistent. It is only from [the aspect of]
the "mundane truth" that [it is said that]
there are various beings. (T 32.333c15-17)
49 - T44.483c14-21.
50 - On the early Chinese interpretations of the two
truths, see Whalen W. Lai, "Sinitic
Understanding of the Two Truths Theory in the
Liang Dynasty (502-557): Ontological Gnosticism
in the Thought of the Prince Chao-ming, "
Philosophy East and West 28, no. 3 (1978);
339-351; "Once More on the Two Truths: What
Does Chi-tsang Mean by the Two Truths as
'Yueh-chiao'?" Religious Studies 19 (1983):
505-521; Paul L. Swanson, "The Two Truths
Controversy in China and Chis-i's Threefold
Truth Concept", chap. 2, sec. 3, and chaps.
4-6; Tokiwa Daijo, Zoku Shina Bukkyo no
kenkyuu, pp. 330-337; Fukushima Kosai, "Ryotai
nitai shiso no tokushitsu," Bukkyogaku seminaa
2 (1965): 45-55, and "Myoho toshite no ennyuu
santai to sono shiso teki haikei, " Otani
Daigakuu kenkyuu nempo 28 (1976): 16-24.
51 - Ta-ch'eng hsuan-lun, T 45.15a15-17. The idea of
"two truths qua instruction" was not invented
by Chi-tsang. According to Chi-tsang it was put
forward by Seng-lang, Seng-ch'uan, and Fa-lang
to counter the Ch'eng-shih masters'
interpretation of the two truths as two
independent ontological principles. see
Ta-ch'eng hsuan-lun, T 45.15a25-27, 22c10-11;
Erh-ti i, T45.86a29-b11; and Chung-kuan-lun su,
T 42.28c19-26. Chi-tsang also mentioned the
Elder Liang of Kuang-chou (in present Kuangtung
Province) , identified as Tao-liang of the
mid-fifth century, as its advocate. See Erh-ti
i, T45.90a24-b6 Also see Sato Tstsuei, "Sanron
gakuha ni okeru yalukyo nitai setsu no keifu,
Ryuukoku Daigaku ronshuu 380 (1966): 12-15.
Recent scholars even trace its beginning back
to Seng-chao and T'an-ying. See the works listed
in note 46 above. As for the scriptural sources
or the idea, Chi-tsang cites, besides the
Otani gakuho 60, no. 4 (1980): 1-10.
P.673
Pa~ncavi.m`satisaahasrikaapraj~naapaaramitaa-su
Pa~ncavi.m`saaayaana Mahaaparinirvaa.na-suutra
and the Sata-`saastra, See Ta-ch'eng hsuan-lun,
T 45.23a8-12, Erh-ti i, T45.78b7-8, 86b11-16;
and Ching-ming hsuan-lun, T 38.894b9-14. 52 -
Erh-ti i, T45.108c17-23.
53 - Ching-ming hsuan-lun, T38.894a16-17. See a
similar passage in Erh-ti i, T45.88c6-9.
54 - Ta-ch'eng hsuan lun, T45.16a10-14.
55 - Ibid., T45.16c26-28.
56 - See note 40 above.
57 - Ta-ch'eng hsuan-lun, T45.15.15b7-10. For
similar remarks, see Erh-ti i, T45.86c1-5.
58 - Erh-ti i, T 45.92c23-26. Chi-tsang continues to
comment that the "two truths qua standpoints"
and the "two truths qua instruction," when
correctly comprehended, are actually not
different (ibid. T 49.93c3-11).
59 - They are referred to as "two truths qua
conditional, provisional names" (yin yuan
ch'ia-ming erh-ti) and "two truths qua
determinate natures" (ting-hsing erh-ti) ,
respectively, in the Ching-ming hsuan-lun, T
38.891c20-892a8.
60 - Erh-ti i, T 45.79b1-10.
61 - Refer to ibid., T45.92c26-93a9.
62 - The "five alternatives" are five different ways
of reading the terms "truth" and "nontruth"
mentioned in the paragraph preceding this
quotation (Ta-ch'eng hsuan-lun, T45.16b12-c3).
63 - Ibid., T45.16c14-20. A more detailed analysis,
on which our explanation of this quotation
below is based, is found in the Erh-ti i, T
45.93c23-94a9.
64 - Fa-hua hsuan-lun, T34.396a25-27. Also see
Erh-ti i, T45.90c2-8.
65 - Fa-hua hsuan-lun, T34.396b19-29. Also see
Erh-ti i, T 45.90c26-91a15.
66 - Unlike Hegel's "positive dialectic," in which
the opposition between two conflicting moments
is resolved in a higher moment incorporating
the elements of the two lower moments, the
"negative dialectic" of the Madhyamaka
reconciles the contradiction between the two
moments of the earlier level by writing off
both of them as objects of attachment to be
abolished at the next level.
67 - Ta-ch'eng hsuan-lun, T 45.15c5-11. Also see
Chung-kuan-lun su, T 42.27c27-28b6.
欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。
下一篇:A fifteenth-century royal monument in Burma and the seven stations in Buddhist art