您现在的位置:佛教导航>> 五明研究>> 英文佛教>>正文内容

Rationality, Argumentation and Embarrassment

       

发布时间:2009年04月18日
来源:不详   作者:V. K. Bharadwaja
人关注  打印  转发  投稿


·期刊原文
Rationality, Argumentation and Embarrassment:
A Study of Four Logical Alternatives (catu.sko.ti) in Buddhist Logic
By V. K. Bharadwaja
Philosophy East and West
Volume 34, no. 3 July 1984
pp. 303-319
Copyright 1984 by University of Hawaii Press
Hawaii, USA

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

p. 303

In this paper I shall consider several interconnected issues centering around the four logical alternatives (catu.sko.ti) in Buddhist logic which, it seems to me, involve questions of rationality, argumentation, and philosophical embarrassment. It is my contention that philosophers who have worked in this area of Buddhist logic during the past fifty years or so have not faced these issues squarely. In their work, they show either an obsession with logic, [1] or a tilt in favor of the Inexpressible, [2] or have felt a certain level of philosophical embarrassment [3] while discussing them. Let me state these issues:

One: In the early Paali Buddhist literature we find (a) not only expressions "There is a next world" and "There is no next world" but also the forms "There is and is not a next world" and "There neither is nor is not a next world" [4], and (b) "The world is finite," "The world is infinite," "The world is both finite and infinite," and "The world is neither finite nor infinite." [5] There are two features of these examples (a) and (b): (1) Regarding them as a subject/predicate form of statement, what is in question in (a) is the existence of the next world (the subject term) in each one of these four expressions; while in (b) the existence of the world, the subject term, is not in question; what is in question is whether or not the world is finite. (2) In both (a) and (b), four logical possibilities have been taken into account: affirmation, negation, both affirmation and negation, and neither affirmation nor negation. These four possibilities have been historically called catu.sko.ti, and philosophers have taken upon themselves the task of explaining them, the question being as to how it is that Buddha, the Enlightened One, rejected each one of them. [6] Naagaarjuna exploits this rejection as a form of argumentation against his critics and opponents. [7] There is a vast historical gap between the date of the Buddha and the date of Naagaarjuna; yet when one reads Naagaarjuna's works one is surprised by the similarity between his work and that of the Buddha -- in the formulation of the four alternatives and their systematic rejection. [8]

Two: Naagaarjuna is said to have held no thesis or philosophic position of his own on the grounds that he rejects each one of the the four possible alternatives and that he himself says that "he has no thesis of his own or no position to defend." [9] The question, however, is that if he has no thesis of his own to defend, then what is he doing? Is he engaged in vitaa, [10] a form of debate in which one is concerned only with refuting the opponent's thesis but not with establishing one's own? An affirmative answer to this question is "an embarrassment to the philosophers," [11] however "useful and effective a philosophic method" [12] it may prove to be.

Three: The above two become issues only when we think that both Buddha,

p. 304

the Enlightened One, and Naagaarjuna, the Maadhyamaka philosopher, were concerned with the Inexpressible. "'All things are void' is not a proposition. It only expresses the Inexpressible with the help of the conventional truth. The real language here would be silence." [13] Or, as Ramchandra Pandeya puts it: Since none of the four alternatives have been asserted, the question of their denial does not arise such that "if there be any reality, it cannot be expressed in terms of four ko.tis." [14]

I will discuss these issues one by one. My plan is as follows: First, I will pick up one or two major positions on each one of these issues and examine them in detail. My strategy is to take into account the context in which these issues make their maiden appearance; to draw important distinctions, like the one between different types of questions; to indicate the role which the Buddhists assign to denying each one of the four possible alternatives in order to reject the opponent's position; and finally to outline the conceptual framework within which both the Buddha and Naagaarjuna are operating. In the course of my argument I suggest that both argumentation and embarrassment presuppose a certain analysis of the concept of rationality which to my mind is too narrow to go with the sense in which we say that 'man is a rational animal'.

In the early Paali Buddhistic literature, [15] four types of questions have been differentiated. (1) There are questions which ought to be explained categorically. For example, to the question "Is form impermanent?" the answer is "Yes, it is." To the question "Is the world full of suffering?" the answer is "Yes, it is." To the question "Does everyone die?" the answer is "Yes, everyone dies." These are questions which are clear in respect of both syntax and semantics and which therefore are answered categorically. The Buddhists call them pa~nha eka.msavyaakara.niiya. [16] (2) Then there are questions which ought to be answered with a counter question. For example, the question "Is consciousness a person's soul or is consciousness one thing and the soul another?" is responded to with a counter question "What do you take to be the soul?" The Buddhists call them pa~nha pa.tipucchavyaakara.niya. [17] (3) A third type of question is those that should be set aside. For example, the question "Will the Tathaagata live after his death or not?" is a question which is to be set aside. Such questions are called pa~nha.thapaniiyo. [18] (4) The fourth type of question is those which ought to be explained analytically and then answered. For example, to the question "Are all human beings reborn?" the answer is "Some are and some aren't." Questions like these are called pa~nha vibhajjavyaakara.niya. [19] In the case of the fourth type, adequate specification, clarification, and analysis are required before these questions are answered correctly. For my purposes, two types of question are important: the first type of question to which a categorical answer is possible, and also is generally given; and the third type of question, those questions which are to be set aside -- that is, the eka.msa and the .thapaniiya questions. The remaining two types of question require clarification and analysis but they are both askable and answerable affirmatively or negatively as the case may be. The questions of evidence --

p. 305

whether that evidence is analytic or empirical or whether it is of some other admissible kind of evidence -- are definitely relevant to the truth and falsity of their answers.

Consider first the .thapaniiya kind of question. A .thapaniiya question is one which is to be set aside. Jayatilleke sees in this type "a modern parallel in the kind of questions which the Positivist dismisses as meaningless and therefore unanswerable." [20] The question, however, is: "What is the criterion by applying which a certain question is said to be set aside? One answer which Buddhaghosa gives is that a .thapaniiya question is "a question which ought not to be explained and which ought to be set aside on the ground that it was not explained by the Exalted one." [21] But as Jayatilleke observes: "This is not very helpful, for he is virtually saying that these questions ought to be set aside because they have been set aside by the Buddha." [22] Buddhaghosa's position thus amounts to accepting the authority of the Buddha, an authority which even the Buddha himself did not regard as unchallengeable, and this is philosophically very embarrassing. We do need a criterion to tell a .thapaniiya from a.thapaniiya question.

Broadly, there are two different criteria for identifying a.thapaniiya question: (1) the pragmatic criterion and (2) the logical criterion. As regards the pragmatic criterion Jayatilleke observes: "These questions were 'to be set aside' (.thapaniiya) on pragmatic grounds since belief in any of the possible answers was considered irrelevant and otiose for our purpose." [23] Here the parable of the arrow is relevant. The parable is designed to bring home the idea that what is important is giving urgent medical attention to the one who is shot with the arrow. Questions such as "Who shot the arrow?" are left to be answered later, when an inquiry into the incident is conducted. In the context of inquiry, these questions are both askable and answerable; but in the context of giving urgent medical aid to the victim, they are irrelevant.

The second is the logical criterion. A .thapaniiya question is either (a) misleading in form, violating the logic of meaningful syntax and thus rendered meaningless, or (b) it is conceptually impossible for us within a given conceptual framework to assign' truth values, true or false, to any answer given to it. Take, for instance, the question whether the Tathaagata will exist after death. An answer to it is classified as one of the avyaakata theses [24] (which we shall discuss presently). From a logical point of view, it should be possible to say that any one of the four alternatives is true. The possible alternatives are [1] 'Yes, it is the case', [2] 'No, it is not the case', [3] 'It is both the case and not the case', and [4] 'It is neither the case nor not the case'. But, on the Buddhist view, none of the four alternatives "fits the case" (upeti). To say that the Tathaagata exists after death does not fit the case; that he does not exist after death does not fit the case; that he exists and does not exist after death does not fit the case; that he neither exists nor does not exist after death does not fit the case. [25] When each of the four possible alternatives is rejected, then within the context in which the question is asked, one obvious conclusion is that it is not possible to answer the question "Does the Tathaagata

p. 306

exist after death?" This possibility is not empirical; and one is led to surmise that it involves logical and conceptual confusions -- for instance, having a good syntax grammatically but semantically having a result that is a meaningless sentence like "The Taj Mahal is kind to people who visit it" or an unaskable question like "Is the father the female parent? " The question, for example, "Where does the flame of a candle go to when it is blown out?" [26] is one which does not admit a meaningful answer because it is based on a conceptual confusion of two distinct logical concepts. (It is interesting to observe that in the early Paali Buddhistic texts an exactly similar example is given. Compare "This fire in front of you, which has gone out, in which direction has it gone?") [27] The question thrives on the mistaken syntactical similarity with another question like "Where do I go when I fall sick?" The second question is perfectly meaningful while the first is incomprehensible. The second admits of a perfectly meaningful answer while the first does not.

There is another type of question which is regarded as "inappropriate" (na kalla) and [28] which, like the .thapaniiya questions, is also set aside on the grounds that it is "literally meaningless." [29] For example, "What is decay and death and of whom is this decay and death?" [30] is an inappropriate question; it is a misleading question to ask "Who feeds on the food of consciousness?" Both are examples of inappropriate, improper questions (na kalla pa~nha). [31]

I said earlier that questions of the first type, namely, the questions which ought to be explained categorically, raise a special problem about the logical status of their answers. To a question of this type like "Is the world full of suffering?" the categorical answer is "Yes, the world is full of suffering." What is the logical status of this answer? Regarded as an empirical statement or an unrestricted empirical generalization it is patently false. But for Buddha, the Enlightened One, it is true with absolute certainty. And we shall see later that his answer to this question is one of the fundamental constituents or presuppositions of the Buddhist conceptual framework. As such, it may be said, it is either analytically true or the question of its truth or falsity within that framework simply does not arise. The only question one can ask about it is "Why after all should we accept this statement that the world is full of suffering as true?" And there is all the difference in the world between saying (1) that a statement S is true and saying (2) that S is accepted to be true. (1) may be a good reason for (2), but it need not be; and from (2), (1) need not follow. Besides, the reasons for (1) need not be the reasons for (2) and conversely also. [32] The question "Why after all should we accept that the world is full of suffering?" is external to Buddha's conceptual framework; and it is decidable on grounds of pragmatic considerations only. [33] Such considerations may not be regarded as rational in the narrow sense of the word "rational," the sense in which giving reasons for the truth of a statement is being rational. But, all the same, they are not irrational, either, for they concern and take into account the reasons for accepting the statement to be true. They

p. 307

involve a necessary reference to our aims, motives, and purposes, to our values, commitments, and concerns, and even to our aesthetic considerations, like simplicity and elegance. In Carnap's terminology [34] such questions are external and not internal to the Buddhist conceptual framework. However, I disagree with Carnap on the point that only because external questions cannot be answered within the given linguistic framework, their answers must be analytically true with respect to the framework. To my mind, they need not be, and in fact they are not analytically true. The statement that the world is full of suffering is not analytically true; rather it expresses our commitments, [35] and whether these commitments are moral, intellectual, or philosophical will depend upon the type of conceptual framework within which we operate.

There is a distinction between vyaakata and avyaakata questions. In the early Paali Buddhist literature we come across four questions which have been characterized as avyaakata. "Vyaakata" means "analysed, explained, clear, comprehensible." [36] Thus a vyaakata question is well-analyzed, explained, clear, and comprehensible such that a meaningful answer to it can be given within the conceptual framework in which it occurs. The question is both askable and answerable within that framework. It is not a .thapaniiya question, a question which is to be set aside. Given the types of questions we have enumerated and differentiated, all questions other than the improper ones (na kalla pa~nha) and those that are to be set aside (.thapaniiya pa~nha) fall within the range of vyaakata questions. The questions which are to be set aside need to be differentiated from those that are improper or misleading. An improper question (na kalla pa~nha) is to be set aside on the grounds that it is "literally meaningless." [37] I shall call them unaskable questions. The question 'What is decay and death and of whom is the decay and death?' [38] and the question 'Who feeds on the food of consciousness?' [39] are improper and misleading questions. They are questions "which are suggested by the grammar of the language but which give or imply a false or distorted picture of the nature of reality. [40] This feature of na kalla questions shows that they form a proper subset of .thapaniiya questions. But then what is the differentia of na kalla questions?

Both types of questions are those which are to be set aside. Both types are grammatically well-formed also. The two may be differentiated on the grounds that while a na kalla question is either improper or misleading, a .thapaniiya question is set aside (a) on the strength of pragmatic considerations formulated on the lines of the parable of the arrow, or (b) on logical grounds with respect to (i) that any answer to them fails to fit the case (upeti) and (ii) that any answer to them results in an avyaakata thesis. Besides, the kind of response which they evoke would differentiate a na kalla from a .thapaniiya question. In the case of na kalla questions, "all four of the logical alternatives may be false," [41] but these questions are not to be treated as .thapaniiya since they have been categorically answered. The Nikaayas distinguish between the two types by using the formula

p. 308

'maa h'evam' (do not [say] so) for all the four alternatives of a .thapaniiya question, while in the case of na kalla questions, "the usual negation 'no h'idam' (it is not so) is used for each of the four alternatives." [42]

We have said above that any answer to a .thapaniiya question results in an avyaakata thesis, a thesis which is unanalyzed, unexplained, is not clear, and is incomprehensible. Such a thesis broadly is of two types: first, that which affirms or denies the existence of the nominatum [43] of the subject term, and second, that which, while presupposing the existence of the nominatum of the subject term, affirms or denies a certain predicate of it. [44] A, example [45] of the first type is:

(A) (1) There is a next world
(2) There is no next world
(3) There is and is not a next world
(4) There neither is nor is not a next world

In (A) it is the existence of the next world which is affirmed in (1), denied in (2), both affirmed and denied in (3), and neither affirmed nor denied in (4). An example [46] of the second type is:

(B) (1) This world is finite
(2) This world is infinite
(3) This world is both finite and infinite
(4) This world is neither finite nor infinite

There are other examples of avyaakata theses; but the difference between them as in (C) below is in terms of the subject and the predicate chosen in a given context; or, as in (E) below, the difference is in terms of the contrary or contradictory predicates affirmed or denied of the subject. An example [47] of (C) is as follows:

(C) (1) The soul is identical with the body
(2) The soul is different from the body
(3) The soul is both identical with and different from the body
(4) The soul is neither identical with nor different from the body.

Here in (C), if (1) through (4) are regarded as subject-predicate forms of the statement, then the difference between (B) and (C) is in the particular subject and predicate chosen in a given context. From the logical point of view, formally there is no difference between (B) and (C).

(D) (1) The Tathaagata exists after death
(2) The Tathaagata does not exist after death
(3) The Tathaagata both exists and does not exist after death
(4) The Tathaagata neither exists nor does not exist after death. [48]

In (D) as in (A) the existence of the nominatum of the subject term is affirmed in (1), denied in (2), both affirmed and denied in (3), and neither affirmed nor denied in (4). An example of (E) is as follows:

(E) (1) The soul is happy
(2) The soul is unhappy

p. 309

(3) The soul is both happy and unhappy
(4) The soul is neither happy nor unhappy.

Here in (E) the predicates affirmed or denied of the subject in (1) through (4) are contrary and not contradictory. [49] An example in which the predicates are neither contrary nor contradictory [50] is as follows:

(F) (1) The goal can be attained by knowledge
(2) The goal can be attained by conduct
(3) The goal can be attained by both knowledge and conduct
(4) The goal can be attained by neither knowledge nor conduct.

Any example in which the predicates are contradictory is the same as (B) or (C) above. In my discussion, I will restrict myself to the forms (A) and (B) only. From the logical point of view, it is the (A) and (B) forms which are interesting and not the others -- at least so it seem to me. The theses (l) through (4) in both (A) and (B) are avyaakata theses. The questions to which they are answers are .thapaniiya to be set aside. In both (A) and (B) each one of the four logical alternatives is rejected. This form of rejection, at the hands of Naagaarjuna, [51] developed into "a very useful and effective philosophic method" [52] called the prasa.mga form of argumentation, [53] that is, the argument by reductio ad absurdum. [54]

What are we to make of the rejection of each one of the four logical alternatives? The ground cited for the rejection is that none of the alternatives fits the case (upeti) . As far back as 1917 Poussin [55] treated the four logical alternatives (catu.sko.ti), as "a four branched dilemma" of Buddhist dialectic. [56] He believes that it violates the law of contradiction. He writes: "Indians do not make a clear distinction between facts and ideas, between ideas and words; they have never clearly recognized the principle of contradiction. Buddhist dialectic has a four branched dilemma: Nirvaa.na is existence, or non-existence, or both existence and non-existence, or neither existence nor non-existence. We are helpless." [57] I wish that Poussin had realized that the old Aristotelian three laws of thought are the mark of human rationality (and on Leibniz' reckoning, [58] even God could not violate them -- in particular the law of contradiction), and it does not matter whether a human being is white, black, brown, yellow, or red. For this reason, if for no other, I do not agree with Poussin that Indians, if they are rational enough, have violated the law of contradiction in rejecting each one of the four logical alternatives. Anyway, Poussin was puzzled about the structure of catu.sko.ti, and he found himself helpless to understand it. But he need not have despaired so very much about it.

Mrs. Rhys Davids [59] calls the rejection of the four logical alternatives "Laws of Thought." She writes: "The import of a number of terms is set out, usually in dichotomic division but sometimes in the distinctively Indian method of presenting the by-us so called Laws of Thought thus, Is A B & If not, is A not B? If not, is A both B and not B? If not, is A neither B nor not B (in other words is A a chimera)?" [60] She regarded the rejection of the second and the third alternatives

p. 310

as an assertion, respectively, of the law of contradiction and the law of excluded middle. [61] Mr. B. M. Barua agrees with Mrs. Rhys Davids but makes the bold statement of calling all four logical alternatives the four laws of thought. He says: "These are in their application to propositions:

1. (If A is B), A is B
2. A cannot be both B and not B
3. A is either B or not B
4. A is neither B nor not B" [62]

It needs little argument to point out Mr. Barua's logical folly. One tends to agree with Jayatilleke that the contentions of both Mrs. Rhys Davids and Mr. Barua, that the four logical alternatives are laws of thought, are equally fantastic. Buddha, the Enlightened One, was not interested in asserting logical truths or inconsistent statements in rejecting any one or all of the four alternatives. Mr. Barua's construal of the rejection of the fourth alternative as an assertion of the law of double negation is beyond comprehension, as it does violence to the common sense and logic that we have learnt from the cradle. [63]

P. T. Raju's interpretation [64] of the rejection of the catu.sko.ti alternatives reduces to this: Each one of the four logical alternatives is about the `suunya (void), which in mathematics means 'zero'. He writes "Zero is the quantity of which all the four alternatives are denied: it is neither positive, nor negative." [65] To my mind, this is an assertion which is the least illuminating; and it turns out to be identical with what was to be analyzed, explained, and made clear, the analysandum. Besides, Raju makes mistakes like conflating the Buddhist notion of avyaakata ("unanalyzed, unexplained, unclear, and incomprehensible") with the Jaina notion of avaktavya [66] ("indescribable"), on the one hand, and with the `Sa^mkara Vedaantic notion of anirvacaniiya ("indefinable"), on the other, a reading which, to my mind, is unwarranted and misplaced. Richard Chi [67] seeks to analyze the four logical alternatives in terms of the first-order functional calculus. He utilizes the truth functional logic also when and where this adds to clarification. This is an admirably effective approach. He opines that if one keeps apart the different levels of truth and the different points of view, the so-called puzzle about the rejection of the four logical alternatives does not arise. [68] Suppose, however, that all four alternatives are denied one and the same subject at the same level of truth and from the same point of view; then the puzzle does arise. [69] How is it possible to negate all four logical alternatives simultaneously? This problem, of course, explains de la Vallee Poussin's helplessness: but at the same time it cries out for a satisfactory solution. Chi's observation that Buddha, the Enlightened One, tackled the four logical alternatives by "not a rejection by negation but a rejection by silence" is noteworthy. [70] Yet, logically, catu.sko.ti remains a puzzle; and there must be some way to solve it. Chi mentions one tack suggested by Jayatilleke [71] -- to construct a solution utilizing the notions developed in the many-valued logics of Lukasiewiez and Lobochevsky -- but Chi himself does not

p. 311

offer a solution to the puzzle on these lines. Instead, utilizing L. E. J. Brouwer and A. Heyting's Intuitionistic negation operator, he formulates the four logical alternatives as

(1) p (2) ﹁p (3) p ^ ﹁p (4) ﹁p ^ ﹁﹁ p.

And there he stops. [72] Chi's own solution has quite an affinity with Jayatilleke's solution of the problem of catu.sko.ti. The core of Jayatilleke's thesis is that we treat not-P (in the four alternatives) as the contrary and not the contradictory of P. He writes: "We maintain that the proposition, natt.hi paro loko, should according to its context be treated as the contrary and not the contradictory of atthi paro loko despite linguistic form. [73] Chi exploits the notion of contrary negation as found in the Intuitionistic logic and reformulates the four logical alternatives so that they could be denied simultaneously. [74] In a way, Chi's solution is a reformulation of Jayatilleke's in the strictly formal logical terminology of the Intuitionist logicians. [75] The value of this sort of solution has implications for the methodology to be employed in the study of Buddhist logic. This, however, is an independent topic which I do not propose to investigate in this paper.

Let us call the operator "﹁" Boolean negation operation and the operator "~" de Morgan negation. Unlike de Morgan negation, Boolean negation has properties such that

A & ﹁A entails B,

and that

﹁A & (A v B) entails B. [76]

The idea of Boolean negation originated in the semantical contexts of relevant logics; but it can be discussed in the context of a four-valued semantics. The motivation for Belnap was to "devise an effective logic for computers (mechanical question-answering systems) to use when there is a real risk that the data-base from which answers to questions are to be inferred may be inconsistent." [77] The four values used are:

T(rue) F(alse) B(oth) N(one)

`T' represents the case in which the person has been told about a certain sentence S that it is true but has not been told that it is false; 'F' when he has been told that S is false but not told that it is true; N' when the person has not been told anything: and 'B' when the person has been told both that S is true and also that S is false." [78] On this interpretation of 'T','F','N', and 'B', using the Morgan negation operation

(1) ~T=F (2) ~F=T (3) ~B=B (4) ~N=N

we can use, on the said four values, Boolean negation operation and get:

p. 312

(1) ﹁T=F (2) ﹁F=T

(1) and (2) behave the same way as in the case of the operation ~ of de Morgan negation: but (3)﹁B = N, and (4)﹁N = B. Here (3)﹁B = N will mean something like this: "If a sentence A is marked as both true and false, then ﹁A cannot be marked as true, since in order for this to be the case it would have to be that A is not marked as true (but it is). And similarly A cannot be marked as false since then A would have to be not marked as false (but it is). So A must be marked as None." [79] Similarly, justification can be given for ﹁N = B. Belnap and Dunn remark: "In a nutshell, the difference between ~ and ﹁ would seem to be that ~ is a kind of 'internal' negation, whereas ﹁ is a kind of 'external' negation. ~ A might be read as 'A is false', whereas ﹁A should be read as 'it is not the case that A is true'." [80] But then how are we to understand "not" in a given context? For, we have made intelligible Boolean negation (﹁)in terms of de Morgan negation (~) . Given this situation, ordinarily the distinction between ﹁ and ~ collapses -- so much so that ﹁ is understood in terms of ~ only -- and "so we have only one kind of negation after all." [81] If this is so, then even the Boolean negation ﹁ cannot be employed with advantage over other alternative interpretations given in terms of de Morgan negation to solve the centuries old puzzle of catu.sko.ti.

We must seek some other tack in order to solve the puzzle, or look at it once again in order to be sure what it really is. To do this I will take into account the context in which the four logical alternatives are rejected, and the purposes which are achieved by rejecting them. The considerations which led this kind of rejection to transform itself into the prasa.mga form of argument [82] will not be out of place here. In this connection, to repeat, consider the (A) and (B) types of the avyaakata theses:

(A) (1) There is a next world
(2) There is no next world
(3) There both is and is not a next world
(4) There neither is nor is not a next world

and

(B) (1) This world is finite
(2) This world is infinite
(3) This world is both finite and infinite
(4) This world is neither finite nor infinite.

The alternatives (1) through (4) in both (A) and (B) are answers to .thapaniiya questions, and the answers are avyaakata theses. The questions are .thapaniiya, since in each one of them at the same time a no kalla question is involved. Further, these alternatives are not negated or denied but they are rejected. The alternatives are rejected by maa'h evam (do not [say] so), and not by no h'idam (it is not so). The avyaakata theses are to be set aside, so the rule says (A vyaakataani thaapitaani). [83] Jayatilleke writes: "When the four alternatives happened to be those of a .thapaniiya

p. 313

pa~nha or a meaningless question all four alternatives were rejected rather than negated because the question in each of the alternatives was not considered to be a proper question (kalla pa~nha)." [84] Jayatilleke shows remarkable insight when he says that "Raju and Bahm have therefore misdescribed [85] their nature as far as the Paali Canonical position is concerned by calling this doctrine that of 'four cornered negation' when it ought properly to be called 'four cornered rejection.'" [86] I fail to understand why Jayatilleke did not follow this important insight but remained obsessed with treating the avyaakata theses from a logical point of view exclusively. If we look at them carefully we find that by characterizing them avyaakata (unanalyzed, unexplained, unclear, incomprehensible) we legislate ourselves out from being in a position to say whether or not each one of them is true or false. Their appraisal in terms of truth and falsity is possible only if we have criteria for their factual evaluation. But where are the criteria? We find them nowhere. The alternative for us is to reject them and set them aside (.thapaniiya).

In a moral context "avyaakata" means "neither good nor bad." In this sense "avyaakata" is used to denote what is "neutral" in moral contexts where "what is indeterminate" (avyaakata) are acts which are neither good nor evil. [87] Jayatilleke suggests that if we extend this application of avyaakata to any one of the four logical alternatives in (A) and (B), we would like to say that the avyaakata theses are logically indeterminate in the sense of being neither true nor false. There are no criteria for their factual appraisal. Nor perhaps can there be any; for their logical status is indeterminate. Given this situation we cannot deny or negate them since we could do this only by presupposing a certain set of criteria for their factual evaluation. In the absence of some methodological conceptual framework within which alone their factual relevance and appraisal is possible, we can only reject them, set them aside.

We do not reject a theory in a vacuum, [88] not least an avyaakata thesis. For rejecting an avyaakata thesis, we need a framework of criteria. Fortunately, in this case we have one in the conceptual framework of the Four Noble Truths. This is shwon by the parable of the arrow. Differentiating avyaakata from vyaakata theses, Buddha, the Enlightened One, remarks: The avyaakata questions are not answered (they are .thapaniiya) and the avyaakata theses are rejected (they too are .thapaniiya) because they are "not useful, not related to the fundamentals of religion, not conducive to revulsion, dispassion, cessation, peace, higher knowledge, realization, and Nirvana." [89] Given this, I shall call it the pragmatic criterial framework in which the avyaakata questions and the avyaakata theses are rejected, set aside (.thapaniiya), not negated or denied. Logic is not relevant here. For, where there is neither affirmation nor negation nor inclusion or exclusion of both, what role does logic have to play? Both logic and the obsession with logic, taking logic to be the only form of rationality, are to be set aside as irrelevant. The catu.sko.ti, which has been considered an "insoluble problem for centuries," [90] simply is not a problem. We saw logic in it where there was none. The result: the problem was

p. 314

not susceptible of solution on the logical plane. Once things are put in their proper, natural place, the problem simply ceases to be a genuine problem. [91]

The catu.sko.ti and the rejection of each one of the four logical alternatives have become in the hands of Naagaarjuna "a very useful and effective philosophic method," [92] called the prasa.mga or the reductio form of argumentation. [93] In using this form of argumentation, the reasoner or "the debater may have no thesis of his own or no position to defend." [94] In this connection, Naagaarjuna is frequently quoted as saying: "If I had any proposition, then this defect would be mine. I have, however, no proposition. Therefore, there is no defect that is mine." [95] On the face of it, this way of argumentation is indeed "an embarrassment to the philosophers." [96] The structure of this method of argumentation is as follows: We consider each one of the four possible logical alternatives (catu.sko.ti) and reject it as untenable. The function is to show that any philosophical position can be shown to be logically discrepant, for it can be stated exclusively in terms of the four possible logical alternatives, each one of which is (or can be) easily rejected. Consider for example:

(G) Things are not originated by themselves;
Nor are they originated by others;
Neither by both; nor without cause;
Therefore, there is no origination. [97]

and,

(H) Nirvaa.na is not an existent;
Nirvaa.na is not a non-existent;
Nirvaa.na is not both an existent and also a non-existent;
Nirvaa.na is not neither an existent nor a non-existent. [98]

None of these four possible logical alternatives is applicable to nirvaa.na. They are not upaadeya [99] in relation to nirvaa.na. The idea underlying (G) is that everything, whether mental or material, is without an intrinsic nature (ni.hsvabhaava). [100] If this is so, then saying (1) that some material thing is produced, or saying (2) that some material thing is not produced, are equally the result of conflating the category of "production" with the category of "material thing." The two categories, which are conceptually different, cannot be logically combined in the way that they are combined in (1) and (2). Syntactically (1) and (2) are correctly formed expressions, but semantically they are avyaakata and hence .thapaniiya (unanalyzed, unexplained, unclear, and incomprehensible, and therefore to be set aside). Similarly in the case of (H), the underlying idea is that the category of `nirvaa.na' and the category of `existent thing' have been conflated in the given four possible logical alternatives, with the result that each one of the alternatives, though syntactically correct, is avyaakata semantically and hence to be set aside. This reasoning follows the rule, namely, that the theses which are avyaakata are to be set aside (avyaakataani thapitaani).

Apparently, the avyaakata theses are indeed correct from the ordinary language

p. 315

point of view. Anybody who rejects a certain thesis in this way must have a certain criterial framework within which he is operating, as we have said earlier. In the case of Naagaarjuna, the framework is definitely not that of formal logic, for in his view, these are both avyaakata and .thapaniiya. Nor is his framework that of the methodology of empirical knowledge (pramaa.nas). He accepts only two criteria of knowledge (pramaa.nas): observation (pratyak.sa) and inference (anumaana). He uses them to decide whether a certain piece of information gained observationally or inferentially is true or false. But in the case of questions about (a) dependent origination (pratiityasamutpaada), (b) voidness (`suunyataa), and (c) nirvaa.na he rejects the applicability of the pramaa.na methodology. [101] If I am right in this thinking, then three things become apparent:

First, Naagaarjuna regards (a), (b), and (c) as the constituents of the conceptual framework within which he is operating when he is engaged in arguing against his critics and opponents. He cannot be said to be arguing against his critics in a vacuum. Matilal is mistaken when he says that "the debater may have no thesis of his own or no position to defend." [102] One can indeed regard (a), (b), and (c) as axioms or the presuppositions of Naagaarjuna's philosophical thought, constituting the background of his arguments against his critics.

Second, nirvaa.na is a way of looking at things. It is a conceptual style (d.r.s.ti). [103] One develops this conceptual style by way of understanding dependent origination (pratiityasamutpaada) and voidness (`suunyataa). Hence, in the case of nirvaa.na, the question whether nirvaa.na is an existent or not simply does not arise. And, once you have this conceptual style (d.r.s.ti), all questions concerning origination and nonorigination, and so forth become irrelevant and need to be set aside.

Third, Naagaarjuna's argumentation, at the same time, works within the conceptual framework of the Four Noble Truths. Being a Buddhist, he cannot, and in fact he does not, give it up. [104] So he says: "All things prevail for him for whom this voidness prevails). Nothing prevails for him for whom voidness does not prevail. [105]

In fact, in Naagaarjuna's thought, all three are interconnected; (a) dependent origination (pratiityasamutpaada) , (b) voidness (`suunyataa), and (c) nirvaa.na constitute the conceptual framework F1 within which he is operating. The aim is to develop the nirvaa.na d.r.s.ti or the nirvaa.na conceptual style. This aim is equally well achieved if the conceptual framework F2 of the Four Noble Truths is accepted; and Naagaarjuna does operate within this framework [106] also. Within the framework F2 the avyaakata theses are set aside on pragmatic grounds of dharma; but with respect to the framework F1 they are rejected on the grounds that within F1 the four possible logical alternatives become avyaakata theses, and outside the framework they make no sense. The ordinary language does permit them, but within Naagaarjuna's conceptual framework F1 they are to be set aside as being external to the framework. However embarrassing it might be to the philosophers, neither formal logic nor the methodology of empirical knowledge can be said to be relevant for an adequate understanding of the so called problem of catu.sko.ti.

p. 316

NOTES
1. Archie J. Bahm, "Does Seven-Fold Predication Equal Four Cornered Negation Reversed?" Philosophy East and West 7, nos. 3 and 4 (October 1957 and January 1958): 127-130; Richard S. Y. Chi, Buddhist Formal Logic (London: The Royal Asiatic Society of Great Britain and Ireland; sold by Luzac and Co., Ltd., 1969); Mrs. Rhys Davids, "Logic (Buddhist)," Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1926), vol. 8, p. 133; K. N. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge (London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1963; reprint, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1980) (hereafter cited as Early Buddhist Theory); P. T. Raju, "The Principle of Four-Cornered Negation in Indian Philosophy," The Review of Metaphysics 7 (1953-1954): 694-713 (hereafter cited as "Four-Cornered Negation"); Richard H. Robinson, "Some Logical Aspects of Naagaarjuna's System," Philosophy East and West 6, no. 4 (January 1957): 291-308; St. Schayer, "Altindische Antizipationen der Aussagenlogik," in Studien zur Indischen Logik, Extrait du Bulletin de l'Academie Polonaise des Sciences et des Letters Cracovic (1933), p. 93: and R. D. Gunaratne, "The Logical Form of Catu.sko.ti: A New Solution," Philosophy East and West 30, no. 2 (April 1960): 211-239 (hereafter cited as "Logical Form"). Gunaratne offers a vehement defense of the application of formal logic (including set theory) to catu.sko.ti statements whose structure, he insists, is isolable and can be given a consistent interpretation. He tends to reject Alex Wayman's view expressed in his article "Who Understands The Four Alternatives of the Buddhist Texts?" (Philosophy East and West 27, no. 1 (January 1977) (hereafter cited as "Who Understands?"): 3-21), that after all it may be "hazardous and probably contraindicated to apply symbolic logic" (p. 5) without reservations to catu.sko.ti. My own position lends support to Wayman's view vis a vis Gunaratne's.

2. Ramachandra Pandeya, "The Logic of Catu.sko.ti and Indescribability," in his Indian Studies in Philosophy (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1977), pp. 89-103 (hereafter cited as "Logic of Catu.sko.ti"); T. R. V. Murti, The Central Philosophy of Buddhism (London: George Allen & Unwin. 1955). Observe in this connection Richard S. Y. Chi's remarks in his article "Topics on Being and Logical Reasoning" (Philosophy East and West 24, no. 3 (October 1974): 298): "After many years of dispute, I still think that Murti's view on this subject is the right one" (hereafter cited as "Topics on Being").

3. B. K. Matilal, The Logical Illumination of Indian Mysticism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977; reprint, New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1978) (hereafter cited as Logical Illumination).

4. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory, p. 134.

5. Chi, Buddhist Formal Logic, p. 161.

6. As in note 1 above.

7. Naagaarjuna's Madhyamaka-`saastra and Vigrahavyaavartani, Buddhist Sanskrit Texts No. 10 (Darbhanga: The Mithila Institute of Post-Graduate Studies and Research in Sanskrit Learning, 1960). For an English translation of the latter work, see Kamaleswar Bhattacharya, The Dialectical Method of Naagaarjuna (Vigrahavyaavartani) (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1978) (hereafter cited as Dialectical Method).

8. Wayman, "Who Understands?" p. 15. "Naagaarjuna, in the matter of the catu.sko.ti is heir to and the continuator of teachings in the early Buddhist canon (in Paali, the four Nikaayas; in Sanskrit. the four AAgamas."

9. Matilal, Logical Illumination, and Vigrahavyaavartani.

10. The Nyaaya Suutras of Gotama, translated by Satisa Chandra Vidyabhusana; reprint, New Delhi: Oriental Books Reprint Corporation, 1975; Matilal, Logical Illumination; Chi, "Topics on Being," p. 295.

11. Matilal, Logical Illumination.

12. Ibid.

13. Bhattacharyya, Dialectical Method.

14. Pandeya, "Logic of Catu.sko.ti."

15. A^nguttara Nikaaya, 5 vols., ed. R. Morris and E. Hardy (London: Paali Text Society. 1885-1900); F. L. Woodward and E. M. Hare, trans., The Book of the Gradual Sayings, 5 vols. (London: Paali Text Society, 1932-1936).

p. 317

16. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory, pp. 281-283.

17. Ibid.. p. 287.

18. Ibid., p. 288.

19. Ibid., p. 281.

20. Ibid., p. 287.

21. Ibid., p. 288.

22. Ibid., p. 288.

23. Ibid., pp. 288, 274.

24. Ibid., pp. 471-476.

25. Majjhima Nikaaya, 3 vols., ed. V. Trenkner and R. Chalmers (London: Pali Text Society, 1948-1951), 1.486; I. B. Horner, trans., Middle Length Sayings, 3 vols. (London: Pali Text Society, 1954-1959); R. Chalmers, trans., Further Dialogues of the Buddha, 2 vols. (London: Pali Text Society, 1888); K. E. Neumann, trans., Die Reden Gotamo Buddho's aus der mittleren Sammlung Majjhimanikaago, vols. 1 and 2 (Leipzig, 1896-1900).

26. Ludwig Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1958), p. 108.

27. Majjhima Nikaaya, I. 487.

28. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory, p. 292.

29. Ibid.

30. Ibid.

31. Ibid.

32. G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903), chap. 5; V. K. Bharadwaja, Naturalistic Ethical Theory (Delhi: University of Delhi Press, 1978).

33. Rudolf Carnap, Meaning and Necessity, 2 ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956).

34. Ibid.

35. Michael Polayni, Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1958).

36. Vaman Apte, Sanskrit English Practical Dictionary (Poona: Prasad Prakashan; reprint, 1977). Richard Chi, in "Topics on Being," mistranslates the Sanskrit "avyaak.rta" as "inexpressible" (p. 296). See Apte's Dictionary. Avyaakata is Paali of Sanskrit avyaak.rta. It means "unanalysed, unexplained, incomprehensible."

37. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory, p. 292.

38. Ibid.

39. Ibid.

40. Ibid.

41. Ibid.

42. Ibid., p. 293.

43. Bertrand Russell, "On Denoting," in Contemporary Readings in Logical Theory, ed. I. Copi and J. Gould (New York: Macmillan Company, 1967).

44. G. Frege, "Sense and Nominatum," and P. F. Strawson, "On Referring." in Copi and Gould, eds., Contemporary Readings in Logical Theory; Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1972).

45. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory, p. 335.

46. Ibid., p. 340.

47. Chi Buddhist Formal Logic, pp. 158-159.

48. Ibid.

49. Ibid.

50. Ibid.

51. Naagaarjuna's Vigrahavyavaartani.

52. Matilal, Logical Illumination, p. 17.

53. Ibid., p. 18, Th. Stcherbatsky, The Central Conception of Buddhism and The Meaning of the Word "Dharma" (Reprint, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidas, 1970), p. 22.

54. Matilal, Logical Illumination, p. 18.

55. Louis de La Valle Poussin, The Way of Nirvaa.na (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1917), p.111.

56. Ibid., p.111.

p. 318

57. Ibid., p. 111. See also F. J. Hoffman, "Rationality in Early Buddhist Four Fold Logic," Journal of Indian Philosophy 10, no. 4 December 1982): 309-337 (hereafter cited as "Rationality").

58. Bertrand Russell, History of Western Philosophy, 1st ed. (London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd., 1946), 2nd ed. (1961), the chapter on Leibniz, pp. 563-576.

59. Mrs. Rhys Davids, "Logic Buddhist," p. 133.

60. Ibid.

61. Ibid.

62. B. M. Barua, A History of Pre-Buddhistic Indian Philosophy (Calcutta, 1921; reprint, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1970), p. 47.

63. For a different line of criticism, see Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory, pp. 334-336. Also see, for some other attempts to solve the so-called problem of catu.sko.ti, Bahm, "Does Seven-Fold?"; Wayman, "Who Understands?"; Hoffman, "Rationality"; Gunaratne, "Logical Form"; and Shosun Miyamoto, "The Logic of Relativity as the Common Ground for the Development of the Middle Way," in Buddhism and Culture, ed. Susumu Yamaguchi (Nakano Press, 1960), pp. 67-68.

64. Raju, "Four-Cornered Negation."

65. Ibid., p. 702.

66. For a clarification of the Jaina notion of avaktavya see V. K. Bharadwaja, "The Jaina Concept of Logic," Indian Philosophical Quarterly 9, no. 4 (July 1982): 363-375.

67. Chi, Buddhist Formal Logic, pp. 156-163.

68. Ibid., p. 161.

69. Ibid., p. 162.

70. Ibid.

71. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory, pp. 333-346.

72. Chi, Buddhist Formal Logic, pp. vii-ix. He writes:
The catu.sko.ti has been considered an insoluble problem for centuries. In December 1967, I read a paper ("A Tentative Solution to the Problem of Four Corner Negation") at the University of Chicago, which I believe solves the problem. The solution depends on applying Bertrand Russell's vicious-circle principle and my explanation of "unavoidable mistakes, " namely, "under cultural circumstance x, a mistaken theory y is inevitable." The paper is unmanageable in length and needs further revision: it will appear as an article. For the moment, I can only say that it corrects my earlier explanation of the catu.sko.ti which is erroneous. (pp. vii-ix of his Foreward [1968] to his Buddhist Formal Logic(1969).

Observe also change in his position reflected in his article "Topics on being and Logical Reasoning," pp. 293-300.

73. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory, p. 343. For Jayatilleke's own solution of the problem, see pp. 333-346.

74. In 1974, Richard Chi came out with the thesis that "Buddhist logic belongs to strictly conventional two-valued logic" ("Topics on Being," p. 297), that he had made a "mistake by comparing catu.sko.ti with intuitionism" (p. 297), and that "the subject of catu.sko.ti... is not at all 'Buddhist logic'" (p. 298). Having said this, he tends to subscribe to T. R. V. Murti's view, and adds: "As a matter of fact, catu.sko.ti is applicable to metaphysical speculations only" (ibid., p. 298).

75. See L. E. J. Brouwer and A. Heyting's work on Intuitionistic logic.

76. Nuel D. Belnap, Jr., and J. Michael Dunn, "Entailment and the Disjunctive Syllogism." Contemporary Philosophy I, ed. G. Floistad (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1981), pp 337-366 (hereafter cited as "Entailment"). See also J. M. Dunn, "Intuitive Semantics for Firstdegree Entailments and Coupled Trees." Philosophical Studies 29 (1976): 149-168, and Nuel D. Belnap, Jr., "A Useful Four-valued Logic," in J. M. Dunn and G. Epstein. eds., Modern Uses of Multiple-valued Logic (Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1977).

77. Belnap and Dunn, "Entailment," p. 342.

78. Ibid., p. 342.

79. Ibid., p. 343.

80. Ibid., p. 343.

81. Ibid., p. 345.

82. Matilal, Logical Illumination, pp. 16-18.

83. Majjhima Nikaaya, I. 426.

p. 319

84. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory, p. 346.

85. Ibid.

86. Ibid.

87. Dhammasa^nga.ni, ed. E. Muller (London: Pali Text Society, 1885); Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory, p. 355.

88. Ludwig Wittgenstein, On Certainty (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1969).

89. Majjhima Nikaaya, I. 431; Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory, p. 357.

90. Chi Buddhist Formal Logic, p. vii.

91. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 3rd ed. (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1968).

92. Matilal, Logical Illumination, p. 17.

93. Ibid., pp. 16-17.

94. Ibid., pp. 16-19. Also compare Chi, "Topics on being."

95. Bhattacharya, Dialectical Method, p. 23.

96. Matilal, Logical Illumination, p. 16.

97. Buddhist Formal Logic, p. 159.

98. Naagaarjuna's Madhyamaka-`saastra, chap. 25, Kaarikaas. 3, 4, 5, 7, and 8.

99. Compare the Paali expression "upeti" ('fits the case').

100. Naagaarjuna's Madhyamaka-`saastra.

101. Naagaarjuna's Vigrahavyaavartani, stanzas 24 to 34.

102. Matilal, Logical Illumination, pp. 16-19. Also compare Chi, "Topics on Being," p. 295.

103. Richard Chi seems to translate "d.r.s.ti" as "dogmatism" ("Topics on Being," p. 296). I agree with him that it is hard to find an English synonym for "d.r.s.ti." But, then, "dogmatism" won't do; "a way of looking at the world" or "a point of view" are better synonyms.

104. Alex Wayman has this important insight when he writes: "the four Noble Truths have been a basic ingredient of Buddhist thinking and attitude" (Wayman, "Who Understands," p. 10). And, again, "Naagaarjuna, in the matter of catu.sko.ti, is heir to and the continuator of teachings in the early Buddhist canon" (Wayman, ibid., p. 15).

105. Naagaarjuna's Vigrahavyaavartani, stanza LXX.

106. In fact, the two frameworks F1 and F2 can easily be shown to be essentially one. The line of argument in that case will be that the framework of the four Noble Truths undergoes linguistic mutation at the hands of Naagaarjuna, as a historical development, into the framework of dependent origination, voidness, and nirvaa.na. (This, however, forms the subject of another paper.)

没有相关内容

欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn


            在线投稿

------------------------------ 权 益 申 明 -----------------------------
1.所有在佛教导航转载的第三方来源稿件,均符合国家相关法律/政策、各级佛教主管部门规定以及和谐社会公序良俗,除了注明其来源和原始作者外,佛教导航会高度重视和尊重其原始来源的知识产权和著作权诉求。但是,佛教导航不对其关键事实的真实性负责,读者如有疑问请自行核实。另外,佛教导航对其观点的正确性持有审慎和保留态度,同时欢迎读者对第三方来源稿件的观点正确性提出批评;
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。