您现在的位置:佛教导航>> 五明研究>> 英文佛教>>正文内容

The Karmic A Priori in Indian Philosophy

       

发布时间:2009年04月18日
来源:不详   作者:Karl H. Potter
人关注  打印  转发  投稿


·期刊原文
The Karmic A Priori in Indian Philosophy
By Karl H. Potter
Philosophy East & West
V. 42 No. 3 (July 1992)
pp. 407-419
Copyright 1992 by University of Hawaii Press

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

 

 

 

p.407

What are we looking for when we look to Indian thought seeking an a priori? One thing that we do find recognized in Indian philosophy is what I shall call "interpretation," which is understood to be distinguishable from the "given." The notion that we--our "minds"--contribute some but not all of what determines our experience is a notion frequently met with in Indian philosophical treatises. There is a series of terms, familiar to those who study Indian thought--terms such as vikalpa and kalpanaa---which might be translated as "conceptual construction." Such constructing or interpreting is viewed by all systems of Indian thought as the mechanism of our ignorance and bondage. But are these conceptual constructions a priori?

The term "a priori" is sometimes used to describe a statement or proposition embedded in an interpretative scheme the structure of which is internally necessary, such that the relations among its constituents are fixed in advance of its application. By extension, the scheme itself comes to be referred to as "the a priori." We say that one can know a priori that 2 + 2 = 4, meaning that it is in some sense inconceivable or impossible that it be otherwise, that the necessity of this truth is independent of counting apples or otherwise applying this structure to experience. By contrast, a contingent or a posteriori judgment is one the truth or falsity of which is not fixed by the structure of the interpretative scheme in which it figures, its truth-value is dependent upon something beyond the internal structure of the scheme.

The question about synthetic a priori truths is one that concerns what determines the fixity of its interpretative structure. Are all a priori statements analytic? That is, is logical consistency among the concepts that figure in the scheme the only consideration determining the necessity or contingency of statements in it? Or are there other factors which might fix the structure of a scheme so as to make it unavoidable for us to interpret things that way? If the latter, there arises the possibility that a statement, a priori because embedded in a fixed scheme, might still be synthetic because it is not "true by definition."

A revered teacher of mine, who had a great influence on the Harvard philosophy that Bimal Matilal and I were involved in at different points in its history, was Clarence Irving Lewis. In his Mind and the World Order Lewis treats the a priori and the given at length in order to repudiate views which ascribe the fixity of an a priori interpretative scheme to sources independent of our decisions. If the scheme is determined entirely by factors beyond our control, our freedom to improve our under standing to make conceptual progress in science and in practical affairs, seems to become illusory. One such view Lewis finds in Kant. Kant locates the a priori principles of sensibility and categories of the understanding

 

 

p.408

in the very nature of human rationality. It is because we are the kind of beings we are, with "minds" limited to developing structures of a sort which reflect human rationality, that we find each other thinking in ways which we can recognize and share, characterized by the familiar relations of time, space, causality, and so forth. Not to recognize and respect these categorical relations is to be irrational, to deviate from the essence of humanity. We have no choice but to think in these categories, says Kant, and that is why a statement such as "every event has a cause" is a necessary truth--to think otherwise would be irrational.

Lewis finds this Kantian conception of the a priori objectionable. In attacking it he sets out an interesting analysis of what the a priori must (or ought to) be, as a way of indicating what is wrong with Kant's notion. According to Lewis' analysis, the a priori must have three properties: (1) It must have features of a sort which will allow us to use it to "catch" the "given" (that is, the data given to us in sensation). Characteristically, we employ the a priori to distinguish "reality" from what is not "real," that is, to tell truth from error, and we couldn't do that, Lewis argues, if our concepts didn't have any features which could match or fail to match the given. (2) It must be "true no matter what," it must legislate rather than report. It cannot be dictated by experience if it is to be useful in organizing that experience. This is the "fixity" of the a priori of which I have spoken.[1] (3) It must be "unrevisable'' in the sense that it is a scheme which we can choose to apply or not to apply, but with which we cannot tamper without destroying it.

Lewis argues that his own conception of the a priori, which he calls the "pragmatic a priori," satisfies these requirements both in letter and in spirit. Where Kant finds the necessity of the categories to be a result of the limitations of human reason, Lewis argues that this necessity derives from our social nature. "The categories," he says, "are our ways of acting," by which he means that it is our practical concerns, including communication with others, which are responsible for the nature of the categories we adopt. The reality which our chosen categories define is a common reality. "Our categories and definitions are peculiarly social products, reached in the light of experiences which have much in common, and beaten out, like other pathways, by the coincidence of human purposes and the exigencies of human cooperation."[2]

It is instructive to compare the implications of this remark with the three requirements just mentioned, and to contrast them with the Kantian conception. The first requirement is that the a priori must have features of a kind which enable it to "catch" or "match" the given. It is doubtful if Kant thought that this was true of his "pure reason," since his "given" has no cognizable features. On the Kantian conception in its most consistent form, the "given," that is, the "manifold," consists of "things-in-themselves" which have no features at all, at any rate no

 

 

p.409

features we can grasp without using our reason. The things-in-themselves do not even possess spatial and temporal locations; they possess neither primary nor secondary qualities. Now if, in spite of all this, one is still inclined to say that the categories must nevertheless "catch" or "match" the given for Kant, it will be in a very mysterious sense, involving a catching or matching which we are unable to verify in principle. It becomes a puzzle on this conception how it is that the givens of our experience could accommodate or resist the application of one category rather than another. In point of fact, there is no experience for Kant prior to interpretation.

By contrast, Lewis' theory of the given grants it features, so that our understanding may either capture it or fail to do so. The given or quale has features. The activity of interpretation is depicted by Lewis as the business of selecting certain of these features--the ones that display repetition or regularity, for instance--and identifying these as the features of "reality" while disregarding the other more chaotic or fleeting characteristics of the given. Lewis thinks of experience as a flowing presentation of sensory qualia. In The Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation he is even led to consider the possibility of an "expressive language" in which we might be able to speak about the given in its nature prior to the application of the a priori. Given this conception, he supposes, it is no longer a mystery how the categories can fit the given.

The second requirement is that the a priori is necessarily true in a fashion completely independent of the given. Kant's a priori fails this requirement. For Kant, the necessity of the a priori stems from the impossibility of our conceiving things otherwise, an impossibility deriving, however, from an assumed fact, namely, that the workings of the human mind are subject to just these limitations. If we legislate to the given, then, it is only in a secondary manner; Mother Nature, or whoever gave us our reason, is ultimately responsible for the "legislation."

Lewis' conception, on the other hand, makes the necessity of the a priori a matter of our decision. We legislate to the given in a fashion analogous to the way that, in stipulating a definition, we legislate linguistic usage. Thus it is hardly surprising that Lewis has no use for the synthetic a priori. The a priori is always analytic for him, in that we can if we wish, and must as long as we are consistent, maintain the relationships among our concepts which they have by virtue of their definitions, definitions for which we (and not Mother Nature) are ultimately responsible. The third requirement of "unrevisability" is adhered to by both Kant and Lewis, but in rather different ways. Kant's a priori is unrevisable in view of who we are; to revise it is merely to become irrational. Lewis will agree that an inconsistent conceptual system is irrational, but urges that what Kant fails to see is that there are indefinitely many possible conceptual systems, each one internally self-consistent and so rational. Though

 

 

p.410

we cannot rationally "revise" such a system, we can reject it, exchange it for another. Indeed, thinks Lewis, this ability to adopt new conceptual schemes is a measure of our freedom, making sense of the pragmatist's affirmation of meliorism as opposed to the "block-universe" quietism which follows in a world in which whatever is must be.

There is a possible misunderstanding about the a priori which Lewis finds himself attending to at length in The Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation. There he controverts a position he dubs "conventionalism." A conventionalist might accept all that Lewis says about the a priori, taking particularly seriously the second point about its analytic character. The a priori is indeed true by definition, says the conventionalist, and thus it is true because of our linguistic conventions. It is our decisions on how to use words which determine reality, and to exchange one conceptual scheme for another involves merely exchanging one set of conventions for another. We saw that Lewis points to the mechanism of stipulative definition as a model or analogue explaining the analyticity of an a priori conceptual scheme. The conventionalist takes stipulation not as an analogy but as itself the very mechanism for exchanging conceptual schemes. To adopt a new scheme is, on conventionalist assumptions, to stipulate new definitions for our terms, or to create an artificially improved "language."

Lewis recoils from this view (which he presumably found in the thought of Harvard colleagues and others of a positivistic bent) since it seems to grant us too much freedom, so much as to make the improvement of our conceptual systems a trivial matter, astonishingly easy. The conventionalist (as Lewis views him) supposes he can make anything the case merely by defining it so. Lewis claims that this is to confuse "sense meaning" with "linguistic meaning," to fail to recognize that a concept embedded in a conceptual system has a character in virtue of that embedding which makes it impossible to redefine it. If it is a necessary truth about our conceptual system that Wednesday is the day after Tuesday (to appeal to his own example), then that necessity is not lessened or removed by defining the day after Tuesday as (say) "Shrewsday." To do this is merely to trade in one name, "Tuesday," for another name, "Shrewsday"; it is not to exchange one conceptual system for another. The "criteria-in-mind,'' as Lewis calls them, which we use to identify what we (now) call "Tuesday" and what we are being asked to call "Shrewsday" are presumably the same, and that is why these are two names for the same thing. If we go farther, but not all the way, in our stipulations we will obviously produce an incoherent scheme which on Lewis' principles is no a priori at all.[3]

Where the Kantian a priori is too rigid, the conventionalist a priori is too flexible. Lewis believed that his a priori, the pragmatic a priori, like Baby Bear's porridge, is just right. Indeed, it is arguable that if we mean

 

 

p.411

by "a priori" what Lewis says we should mean by it--a concept answering to the three requirements I have indicated--then only the pragmatic a priori is a genuine a priori, the Kantian and conventionalist a prioris not answering to all the requirements. This is a verbal point, needless to say, and I shall assume that Lewis' requirements are not definitive of the notion of a priori but rather constitute a recommendation or theory about the nature of what the a priori should be.

Now: is there an a priori in Indian thought? For there to be one, it would seem that it would either have to be analytic, as the conventionalist and pragmatic conceptions hold it to be, or, if in part synthetic, it would have to be "necessary" in some way that makes it impossible for us to revise that synthetic part, as in the Kantian conception of the forms and categories.

I do not think there is any systematic concept of analyticity in Indian philosophy. Characteristic symptoms of analyticity are absent from what Indians think and say about necessary relationships. Sanskrit doesn't have terminology to distinguish "necessary" from "regular" or "lawful." They use such terms as virodha or asa.mbhava both in contexts where we should be likely to say "impossible" as well as in contexts where we should say "contrary to fact."

Consider the kinds of examples of empty terms which one finds scattered through the pages of Indian technical philosophy. One favorite among such illustrations is "the son of a barren woman." Others, used for exactly the same purposes, are "sky-flower" or "hare's horn." We would say that it is impossible for there to be a son of a barren woman because to be barren means to have no children, while the nonexistence of flowers growing in the sky, or of horns growing on rabbits' heads, is a matter not of meaning but of fact. It is not logically impossible, we intone, for a flower to grow in the sky, or a horn on a hare's head; these conceptions are not self-contradictory, as "son of a barren woman" is. Yet Indian thought regularly assimilates all these instances into a single sort.

Definitions do not work in Indian thought the way they do in ours. The Sanskrit term we translate into English as "definition" is lak.sa.na. Lak.sa.na means a "mark," a feature by which we demarcate or recognize the definiendum (in Sanskrit, the lak.sya). Likewise, when Westerners offer a definition they specify a feature or group of features by which one may demarcate or recognize the definiendum, call it X. But that a feature demarcates or brings on the recognition of something is not sufficient to qualify that feature as a definition. That a feature is a defining characteristic of X can be challenged by asking whether something lacking that feature would still be called an X. Thus to say that Y is a defining characteristic of an X is to say that Y is a logically essential characteristic, that the presence of Y is a logically necessary condition for anything to

 

 

p.412

be an X. By contrast, an Indian definiens is satisfactory merely if in fact it does not overlap or "underlap" the definiendum. Therefore to be "true by definition" in Indian thought is merely one way of being true; it is not a different kind of truth ("logical truth").

We do not find speculations about possible worlds in Indian thought of the kind that has become respectable in modern analytic philosophy. Indians don't believe that their reason is capable of exploring other possible worlds. That there are other actual worlds is a commonplace assumption among Indians, entrenched in their psyches by a grand tradition of myth and legend. But Indian philosophers agree that whatever we know about those worlds we know ultimately through the testimony of those who have been there--we can't reason out what it must be like there. Or at least if we can they aren't interested.

Many writers have remarked on the lack of "formal'' logic in India. There is no concern to discover the structure of validity as distinct from the procedures of sound inference. The notion that from "all pigs have wings" and "my Bessie is a pig" I can validly infer "my Bessie has wings" never seems to have occurred to classical Indian logicians.[4] At least there is no explicit discussion of formal validity. Now one may insist that it must "be there" anyhow--but that is not my point; my point is about what they thought, not about what we may think they ought to have thought.

Along with the lack of explicit attention to formal logic one must marshal the point that mathematics, though an Indian science, has little or no connection with Indian logic. Indian logicians do not appeal to mathematical examples as paradigms, nor to mathematical truth as a model of, or extension of, or even analogy to, logical truth. There is no logical truth distinct from factual truth, so far as I can tell, in classical Indian philosophy.

The Indian conception of interpretation, then, is neither of the pragmatic nor of the conventionalistic variety, since Indians do not confine necessity to analytic relationships. But what about the Kantian variety of a priori, which allows for synthetic a priori judgments but locates their necessity in the limits of human reason? is the Indian conception like that?

The answer is no. Classical Indian thought insisted that we can reject our conceptual categories and replace them with others. I do not think Indians even supposed that this must be done holistically: their view allowed for piecemeal revision of a conceptual system. Lewis deems such a scheme insufficiently rigorous to allow for its application to the given. Certainly it seems to present problems for those attempting to follow the development of theories if the meaning of a term may change in the course of the development. But some have viewed this as a standard feature of dialectical progress, and Indian thought is full of dialectical arguments involving shifts of "levels." More disturbing would be the possibility that every term can mean anything at all, and something

 

 

p.413

different from moment to moment. With such a chaotic instrument to try to catch a given and hold it long enough to identify it, relating it to others would be a chancy business--and how would we know when we had succeeded?

Interpretation, even if not a priori, should have some structure, some fixity over at least the period of inquiry, it seems. Does the Indian concept of interpretation grant it even that much? Certainly. It is time for me to attempt to say in positive terms what the Indian conception of interpretation is.

Despite their rejectability and even revisability, within limits Indian conceptual constructions are not random or chaotic. The general assumption governing the Indian account is that our concepts are generated by our karmic inheritance, and that within the limits of the theory of karma it can be manipulated, revised, or exchanged for something else. Let me call this the "karmic a priori," for even though it lacks the features which Lewis requires of a true a priori, or even the features that Kant's a priori has, it is supposed to have the same general function that those a prioris have, namely, to order our experience into "true" versus "false," "real" versus "unreal." That it can do this requires that it have some regularity of structure in advance of the given, on pain of our not being able to tell whether any worthwhile ordering has been accomplished. Without some a priori, language and thought would not occur at all.

According to the karmic a priori it is not the limitations of human reason which determine the categories of interpretation that we use. It is rather those habits of mind that have been generated from past lives. These habits are held by Indians to be the outcome of two kinds of conditioning factors. On the one hand are what are called vaasanaas, rather general dispositions toward the taking of certain sorts of attitudes which help lead to the development of certain sorts of beliefs and desires. These vaasanaas cooperate with more specific factors arising from specific acts in past lives, factors referred to as sa.mskaaras, "traces," or more specifically as karmaa`saya, "karmic residues."

It is difficult but not altogether impossible to gather information about the working of these factors from the textual materials. There is an irritating tendency to treat karma as a well-known matter which needs little explanation and sometimes none at all. Still, there are clues. For example, in the Yogasuutra and its major commentary the Yogabhaa.sya of Vyaasa, we get a clear suggestion that the vaasanaas and sa.mskaaras of a human existence arise from past human existences and not one's former lives as other animals or other kinds of beings. We can infer this from passages which tell us that the karmic forces activated when one is born as a cat are feline dispositions and traces arising from a former feline existence.[5] It is evident that the parallel point follows for a human being. Thus there is a sense in which a sort of Kantian conception is reflected: if

 

 

p.414

"human rationality" is a set of dispositions (to "reason," that is, to think in a rational way) and if that is regularly present in any human existence or condition, then its presence is determined by causes which are outside that existence or condition but which are nevertheless in a sense the result of our free choice, albeit a choice exercised in the past. Let me explain.

According to what we may call the "philosophical" version of karma theory (there are many popular versions which deviate widely), each time one is born, a certain portion of one's karmic residues are tabbed to be "activated" and thus "burned off" during the coming lifetime. This portion is known as one's praarabdhakarman, the karma that is due to mature during the present birth. Since there is a definite time that it will take for just these residues to mature, it is also held that at the time of birth one's length of life is determined by the same mechanism. The maturation or "burning off" of these residues is accomplished through one's having appropriate sorts of experiences. Thus there is a sense in which one's experiences are determined by the karmic residues they burn off. Now as one goes through life having experiences and thus burning off old karmic residues, one performs new actions and lays down new residues which in turn will have to be burned off at some subsequent point either in this life or another. It is debatable just to what extent the nature of one's actions is determined by Past residues; obviously, if the determination were complete this would lead naturally to a kind of fatalist feeling ("I am at the mercy of my past karma and can't do anything about it"), a fatalism which has been felt, by some who have studied Indian attitudes, to have led to villagers' passivity and to quietistic teachings in certain kinds of Indian literature. In philosophical contexts, however, it is not construed that way, since philosophical writings clearly assume the ability of individuals to change their attitudes and beliefs, to perform actions the results of which will bring pleasure in the future rather than pain, or to achieve a kind of awareness of things which leads to cessation of action and release from transmigration. One suspects that such a change of heart and mind will involve revising one's vaasaanas, the general dispositions which incline us toward certain kinds of concerns rather than others, and this suspicion is born out in several ways, though one would like a more straightforward statement to that effect somewhere in the texts.

If we adopt the nonfatalistic, philosophical reading of the karma theory as sketched above and construe our a priori conceptual scheme as a function of karmic causes such as vaasanaas, we get a kind of a priori which is both fixed and revisable. It is fixed in that those karmic residues which are due to mature in this lifetime are going to do so regardless of what choices, decisions, or even changes of attitude and belief we may make or undergo during this lifetime. The power of praarabdhakarman is

 

 

p.415

judged to be considerable. `Sa.mkara, for example, holds that persons who have achieved release from bondage during a human existence must still experience the fruits of their praarabdhakarman, and he is followed in this by many other theorists. We may say, then, that inasmuch as the maturing of one's praarabdhakarman involves our viewing things as human beings do rather than as cats do, the human vantage point must be maintained until the conclusion of this lifetime. To that extent there is no possibility of rejecting the a priori or exchanging it for some completely different scheme.

Yet inasmuch as we are only sometimes human beings, but sometimes cats and so forth, human rationality is not an unavoidable inheritance. Not that we would perhaps choose to be a cat--but many would sensibly choose to be a god, since the divine state is held forth in Indian thought as a genuine kind of birth. However, that is to blur my present point somewhat, which is that even though we must in a given human lifetime maintain our reason insofar as it is an expression of our praarabdhakarman, we can attempt to condition our future dispositions so that future lives, or even the future part of this one, will be different than otherwise. It is never suggested that this will be easy. But what is suggested is that one can with difficulty repress--though not to the point of exclusion--one's inherited vaasanaas and replace them with others deemed preferable.

The texts especially speak of this process in connection with the gaining of release from bondage to karma altogether. The various instruments of such change include, notably, yoga and meditation as well as devotion to God and overt habituation to righteous kinds of activity. The purpose of any of these is to produce a change in one's ways of interpreting the given, in one's a priori if you will, or perhaps to eliminate the interpretative process altogether, at least in the sense of no longer taking its categories seriously, of not being attached to it. Which conception of release and which type of instrument one should prefer are what mainly distinguish the Indian schools of philosophy from one another.

Thus we are brought back to the term vikalpa or "conceptual construction," which I suggested at the outset is the closest Sanskrit term to "a priori." Many Indian schools view vikalpa as that specific factor which occasions bondage, and whose removal must yield release or liberation.

For example, the Yoga systems of both Hinduism and Buddhism spend a lot of time on vikalpa. The Buddhist variety expounded by such writers as Dignaaga and Dharmakiirti takes the external world to be a construction. Whether it is a construction from a given with features which the constructions match or fail to match is a puzzle which scholars are not altogether clear about. Both classical Indian writers and modern Western scholars have apparently thought that the given in this type of Buddhism is like Kant's things-in-themselves, without features that we

 

 

p.416

can identify, although closer inspection of Buddhist texts of this school raises questions about that interpretation.

Another type of Buddhist Yoga system, championed by Vasubandhu, seems to have thought that it is karma which is responsible for the given as well as for the constructions or interpretations of it. Vasubandhu's argument is that our experiences are determined by our karmic residues in exactly the way other Indian philosophers believe our dreaming experiences are. In dreams, it is commonly believed, the mind projects visual, tactile, and so forth sensations and proceeds to interpret them as bases for (dream) beliefs and actions, thus working off more of its karmic baggage. Vasubandhu sees no reason to suppose this is not true of all experiences, waking as well as dreaming.

Pata~njali's Yoga system finds the function of construction as leading to confusions between idea, word, and object and, as a result, to the development of our characteristic interpretative categories. Pata~njali, the author of the Yogasuutras, counsels practicing, at a crucial stage in the yogic meditative process, attainment of a kind of trance state called nirvikalpaka samaadhi, in which one directly confronts the object as it is in itself, without any linguistic or conceptual distinctions obscuring this clear insight. This would seem to imply that, contrary to Buddhist Yoga, Pata~njali believes that there are objects "out there" with identifiable features.

In the Advaita Vedaanta system pioneered by Gau.dapaada, Ma.n.dana Mi`sra, and `Sa.mkaraacaarya, there is constant interplay between the notions of construction, by which we interpret the given, and creation, by which someone--is it Cod or ourselves?-generates the given. All conceptual distinctions are the product of construction, which is viewed as always involving the making of distinctions. The appreciation that distinction or difference (bheda) is a nonapplicable category, that discriminating is the source of bondage, is fundamental to the realization which is self-knowledge and release. Yet `Sa.mkara is unwilling to side with Vasubandhu in assigning the determination of the given to our minds, even though he has often been taken to be an idealist of that sort. in fact, he regularly insists that any constructing requires a ground. Ultimately that ground is undifferentiated Brahman, so that one may still be unsure whether `Sa.mkara really admits the mind-independence of the given in any interesting sense. Still, some Advaitins--perhaps including Gau.dapaada--have located the source of the given in God's handiwork. God is the cause of the world, as the Brahmasuutras tell us. The mechanism by which God manages to create the world is termed maayaa. God controls this maayaa, not we; but the given is manipulated in a fashion designed to suit our karmic requirements. Thus in an indirect sense our karma may control the given. Advaitins generally tend to reject the notion that we mentally construct the world out of whole cloth, so to speak. Exploration

 

 

p.417

of the relation between God's creation and our interpretation is dilated upon by later Advaita scholiasts.

All the systems surveyed in the last few paragraphs agree that constructing is the source of bondage, that thinking and talking are ultimately the enemy, the removal of which constitutes the liberation sought by both Hindu and Buddhist thinkers. An important exception to this linguaphobic tendency is to be found in the twin schools of Nyaaya and Vai`se.sika, accompanied by the philosophical branches of Miimaa.msaa founded by Kumaarila and Prabhaakara. These systems connect the formation of concepts closely with the registering of givens. As they see it, when our senses interact with an object of a certain kind, the mind cannot help but record the presence of a property instantiated in the particular datum. We construct neither givens nor concepts out of whole cloth, they insist. Erroneous understandings arise from the misrelating of givens, not from projecting inappropriate mind-constructed concepts upon them. God creates a world in accordance with our karmic requirements but independent of our wishes (or, in the Miimaa.msaa systems, it is just primordially there). We commerce with this real external world through our sense organs, and as long as we continue to do so we are in bondage. To gain release it will not be enough to stop misinterpreting the given; we shall have to purify ourselves so that we no longer reach out through our organs to commerce with the world at all. In Nyaaya-Vai`se.sika there are "constructions" (vikalpa) but what Naiyaayikas mean by that term is the interrelating, for purposes of recognition and language, of characterized givens, givens not themselves supplied by construction. We may interrelate these givens successfully or unsuccessfully, which is to say, we may frame true or false cognitions about them, but as long as we interrelate them at all we are subject to and creating further karmic traces. And we shall go on interrelating them unless and until we lose interest in the world altogether because of our nonattachment to, our disinterest in, what goes on there. It will still go on, though, stimulated (by God in the case of Nyaaya) in accordance with the karmic requirements of others not released.

Though these systems hardly begin to exhaust the distinctive varieties of Indian speculation on the relations among karma, the given, and the a priori, they may serve as examples. We have, even in such a truncated sampling, a spectrum of views running from Vasubandhu's idealism to Vai`se.sika realism. Here "idealism" means "both given and interpretation mind-dependent," while "realism" means "neither given nor interpretation mind-dependent," and there are compromise positions up and down the spectrum for which names will have to be invented. But for all of these views, realistic or idealistic or in between, the interpretation is karmically dependent, either as arranged by God or mechanically in God's absence, on one's past actions and the habits of conceptualizing they determine.

 

 

p.418

Then--is there an a priori in Indian thought?" "Well, it depends what you mean...." Questions requiring that kind of answer most often should be rephrased, and that is likely the case here. It seems to me that what is interesting is not so much what "a priori" should be understood to mean, but rather what sort of necessity characterizes an interpretative scheme, what is responsible for that necessity, and what we can do about it.

For the traditional empiricist the necessity of the interpretation lies in the relations among the terms or meanings constituting it, relations which define that very conceptual scheme and without which we would not have that scheme but something else. The source of the necessity lies in that definitional constituting, and what we can do about it is to exchange it for another one with different definitions but equally strict in its relationships. Both Lewis himself and his "conventionalist" are types of traditional empiricist: they differ over the source of the necessity. While the conventionalist allegedly finds that source in our conventions of the moment, however whimsical, Lewis locates the source in our common interests as social beings having to rub against each other in active communication and practical carryings-on. As a result, while the conventionalist may view the exchanging of conceptual schemes as a technical exercise-- relatively simple given enough of the kinds of materials that a computer, say, commands: time and tape--Lewis sees it as much more difficult, involving insightful changes in our ways of getting along with one another, new ways of thinking which are accepted by practically everyone as nontrivial solutions to common problems. Both Lewis and the conventionalist accept the existence of an independent world of givens, data of sense which our interpretation must match on pain of eventual rejection. Failure to match these givens is precisely what leads us to consider exchanging our present scheme for another.

The traditional empiricist considers himself liberal, in contrast to the Kantian, in that he allows to us the ability to exchange conceptual schemes. For the Kantian, the only way we could exchange a conceptual scheme would be to graduate from the human state to something nonhuman--and since we cannot as humans conceive what that might be with any real clarity, he is not inclined to follow that thought very far. The Kantian believes that the necessity of the interpretative scheme we have stems from the structure of the human mind. We can't do anything about it, it would seem, except to recognize its implications. Among these are the featurelessness of the given for us, and thus the impossibility of making sense of the notion that a concept matches a given. The reverse side of that coin is that it is likewise impossible for us to know whether any of our concepts, however necessary and fundamental they are (God, freedom, and so on), represent anything other than internal whirrings of the apparatus of "pure reason."

 

 

p.419

The Indian or "karmic" position is not a logical alternative to these, but a way of considering things which makes possible in principle analogues to these and other views about interpretation and the given, yet without involving the triviality of the conventionalist, the practical urgency and implicit publicity of the pragmatist, or the conservatism of the Kantian. The interpretation, the karmic a priori, was determined by us, the karmic account holds, through our past actions. It is fixed by the products of those actions-dispositions and traces--and its necessity derives From that. Yet we can, by future actions, revise the products of our actions so that what is determined will be different in the future from what it has been up to now. We can do this without becoming any less human, and our conceptual scheme may become different as a result. We can, say many Indian wise men, improve our interpretations morally and spiritually and gain heaven in another birth. But we should, if we are truly wise, stifle our interpretations altogether. None of this settles the question about the nature and source of the given. Perhaps it is featureless--Brahman. Perhaps it does have Features, in as Nyaaya, and we can discover what its features are. Perhaps, although it has features, we cannot discover what they are. Perhaps we cannot even know whether or not it has features. Perhaps, says the wise man, it doesn't really matter. Perhaps not, if you're a wise man.

 

 

 

NOTES

1 - Lewis says that "The paradigm of the a priori in general is the definition" (Clarence I. Lewis, Mind and the World Order [New York: Dover Publications, 1929], p. 239)--because definitions legislate meaning rather than report facts.

2 - C. I. Lewis, "A Pragmatic Conception of the a Priori," in Readings in Philosophical Analysis, ed. Herbert Feigl and Wilfrid Sellars (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1949), p. 239.

3 - l think Lewis' strictures here were in fact heeded--although perhaps not even needed--by his opponents: the holism of Quine's "Two Dogmas" and the Kuhnian picture of scientific revolution are cases in point, even though the notion of "criteria-in-mind" remains something of a whipping boy, suggesting a procrustean urge to hypostatize meanings.

4- A possible exception might be urged in the case of late Buddhist logic as in Dharmakiirti, but even here the case is debatable.

5 - Cf. Pata~njali, Yogasuutra IV.2-3, and Vyaasa's Bhaa.sya thereon.

没有相关内容

欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn


            在线投稿

------------------------------ 权 益 申 明 -----------------------------
1.所有在佛教导航转载的第三方来源稿件,均符合国家相关法律/政策、各级佛教主管部门规定以及和谐社会公序良俗,除了注明其来源和原始作者外,佛教导航会高度重视和尊重其原始来源的知识产权和著作权诉求。但是,佛教导航不对其关键事实的真实性负责,读者如有疑问请自行核实。另外,佛教导航对其观点的正确性持有审慎和保留态度,同时欢迎读者对第三方来源稿件的观点正确性提出批评;
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。