The place of Buddhism in Santayanas moral philosophy
·期刊原文
The place of Buddhism in Santayana's moral philosophy
by John Magnus Michelsen
Asian Philosophy
Vol. 5 NO. 1 Mar.1995
Pp.39-59
Copyright by Asian Philosophy
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
ABSTRACT Within the moral philosophy of the Spanish-American
philosopher George Santayana (1863-1952), reference to Buddhism
becomes an essential feature in his formulation of the notion of
post-rational morality, which is that 'phase' of morality which
involves an effort to subordinate all precepts to one that points to
some single eventual good. Post-rational morality is synonymous with
the spiritual life, an essential feature of which is detachment; and
this is why the Buddhists can be said to be the 'true masters' of the
subject. Santayana's claim that Buddhism "suffers from a fundamental
contradiction" can also be seen as an opportunity for us to deepen our
own understanding of that philosophy.
Like so many other philosophers whose origins were in Europe of the 19th
century, the Spanish-American philosopher George Santayana (1863-1952) had
strong affinities with the systems of thought of ancient India, and
Buddhism in particular. Although Santayana's knowledge of Indian philosophy
was not extensive, it was--I believe--deep. The most interesting aspect of
the relationship between Santayana's philosophy and that of India may well
be the fact that Santayana developed almost exclusively within the Western
tradition a philosophy which is very much akin to Buddhism. It is therefore
appropriate to talk of affinity rather than of influence. This affinity
finds its expression in Santayana's thoroughgoing scepticism, in his
conception of the spiritual life, and in his moral philosophy. Although
these three facets of his thought are interdependent, it is primarily upon
an aspect of his moral philosophy that I will focus in this paper. What I
will show is that reference to Buddhism becomes an essential feature in his
formulation of the notion of post-rational morality, which is that 'phase'
of morality which involves an effort to subordinate all precepts to one
that points to some single eventual good. Post-rational morality is
synonymous with the spiritual life, an essential feature of which is
detachment; and this is why the Buddhists can be said to be the 'true
masters' of the subject.
In order to understand this notion of post-rational morality, it has to be
placed in the larger context. Santayana distinguishes three phases of
morality: pre-rational morality, rational ethics, and post-rational
morality. Although there is the suggestion that these are successive stages
in the development of a culture, and that the so-called post-rational phase
is borne of despair and belongs to the ages of decadence, this is not
really his considered view. The three phases are aspects of moral life
which may be realised in the same moment, even though one phase or another
may be most clearly manifested in a particular individual or culture in a
particular historical period.
That aspect of morality which is said to be pre-rational has to do with the
foundation of morality, and the fact that this is said by Santayana to be
'morality proper' betrays the fundamental relativism and naturalism of his
position. According to this view, morality is rounded on instinct and
expressive of passion; it exists on the level of radical elementary
preferences, accommodating a multiplicity of goods which are ultimately
unstable in themselves and incompatible with one another. To deem anything
good is to express certain affinities between that thing and the person
forming that judgement; and the judgement is unassailable provided that the
affinity is real, which means that the judgement is based on adequate
self-knowledge and knowledge of the thing in question. This qualification
shows that Santayana's relativism is not of the naive and sophomoric kind
according to which the mere opinion that something is good is unassailable.
Santayana's relativism is not one of opinion but of nature; it is therefore
inseparable from his naturalism. This naturalistic conception of the good
is sometimes elaborated in terms of the notion of intent, which has to do
with the active operation and the forward-directed character of action. In
order for a thing or a situation to be deemed to be really good, it must
somehow respond to that intent, which sets up its own standard and forms
the basis for moral judgement. Although intent does not rest upon any moral
principle, being itself the basis of moral principles, it does rest upon
the physical habit and necessity of things; it rests upon "the propulsive
essence of animals and of the universal flux, which renders forms possible
but unstable and either helpful or hurtful to one another". [1]
This appeal to nature rather than opinion does not form the basis for any
sort of absolutism. Desires, ambitions, and ideals come into conflict not
only between individuals, nations and religious traditions, but also within
each individual. It is possible that agents in conflict may be so far apart
in nature and ideals that if they meet they can meet "only to poison or to
crush one another". As far as conflicts between humans are concerned,
however, it is possible that the humanity in them is "definable ideally ...
by a partially identical function and intent". If so, it is possible to
rise above their mutual opposition by studying their own nature, and they
may come to realise that they "were hardly doing justice to themselves when
they did such great injustice to others". [2]
And it is here that rational ethics comes into play, for the principles of
harmony, synthesis, and integration are here central. Rational ethics is a
theoretical attempt to bring order into the chaos of the instincts and
impulses which form the basis of morality and are by Santayana labelled
'pre-rational morality'. Pre-rational or 'intuitive' morality, as he also
calls it, is adequate as long as it simply enforces "these obvious and
universal laws which are indispensable to any society"; but it is not
adequate to resolve conflicts between rival authorities: for that it is
necessary to appeal to "the only real authority, to experience, reason, and
human nature in the living man". [3]
It is worth noting at this stage that, whereas Santayana speaks of
pre-rational and post-rational moralities, he speaks of rational ethics.
Why is this? Is there no such thing as rational morality? In a very real
sense no, for a rational morality would imply not only perfect
self-knowledge but also perfect knowledge of the world and others, and--in
fact--a perfect sympathy with the goods of others. This kind of morality
has never existed and it is in fact beyond our reach. In lieu of a rational
morality we therefore have rational ethics, which for Santayana is the mere
idea of a rational morality. In the absence of perfect self-knowledge and
perfect sympathy, which would entail perfect humanity and perfect justice,
we may observe "the general principles of these ideal things [and] sketch
the ground-plan of a true common-wealth". [4] The true masters of this
science are for Santayana--and not surprisingly--the ancient Greeks, and
above all Socrates, Plato and Aristotle. But to say this is not to claim
that ancient Greek society embodied a perfectly rational morality, which
veneration of the Greeks might lead one to attribute to them if one did not
make this distraction between morality and ethics.
Central to the concerns of rational ethics is the phenomenon of volition.
The will is the expression of an animal's living interest and preference
and manifests therefore a radical bias. It is the role of reason to render
will consistent and far-reaching. Rational ethics, unlike the pre-rational,
seeks to be complete; and, unlike intuitive morality, rational ethics rests
upon the impulse to reflect. Reflection upon the individual and society,
upon self and other, reveals that:
Sympathy and justice are simply an expression of the soul's interests,
arising when we consider other men's lives so intently that something
in us initiates and re-enacts their experience, so that we move partly
in unison with their movement, recognise the reality and initial
legitimacy of their interests, and consequently regard their aims in
our action, in so far as our own status and purposes have become
identical with theirs. [5]
This rational reflection, which demands consistency and completeness, also
demands that existence be viewed as a whole; and it shows that, although
the instincts and preferences upon which morality rests are individual,
egoism is not a particularly rational position to adopt; for there is
something quite problematic about the notion of the individual self: "the
same principle that creates the ideal of a self creates the ideal of a
family or an institution". [6] The reason for this is that what a
biographer may define as an individual's life is ultimately not a
significant unity: "All the substances and efficient processes that figure
within it come from elsewhere and continue beyond; while all the rational
objects and interests to which it refers have a transpersonal status". [7]
(Although Santayana does not at this point make reference to it, affinities
with the Buddhist doctrine of Anatta are quite apparent.) Another way to
express the inadequacies of an ethics of egoism and metaphysics of the self
is to show that there is a significant difference between pleasure and
happiness: if the former can be said to be the satisfaction of instinct or
the aim of impulse, the latter is the aim of reason: "The direct aim of
reason is harmony; yet harmony, when made to rule in life, gives reason a
noble satisfaction which we call happiness." The reason why happiness
belongs in the realm of the rational is that it is impossible without
discipline, and this is something the intuitive moralist rejects.
It is discipline that renders man rational and capable of happiness by
suppressing without hatred what needs to be suppressed to attain a
beautiful naturalness. Discipline discredits the random pleasures of
illusion, hope, and triumph, and substitutes those which are
self-reproductive, perennial and serene, because they express an
equilibrium maintained with reality. [8] These effects of discipline
are not unrelated to the element of sympathy touched upon above.
Sympathy has a natural base in such things as parental and sexual
instincts, but in order to find one's happiness in the exercise of
this sympathy, one has to "lay one's foundations deeper in nature and
to expand the range of one's being". [9]
If it is the role of rational ethics to bring order and harmony to the
multifarious and conflicting individual instincts and passions, to promote
happiness through the deepening and expansion of one's being and to
demonstrate the untenability of the egoism/al-truism and the self/other
dichotomies by adopting a holistic point of view through reflection upon
experience--what need is there for anything other than pre-rational
morality transformed by rational ethics? Why bring in or establish a third
phase, post-rational morality? I believe Santayana's answer lies ultimately
in the fact that rational ethics is, as mentioned above, a system of
thought: it is the mere idea of rational morality. Human history shows that
such rational structures of thought do not translate into rational modes of
behaviour, and to Santayana, given his general philosophical position, this
is not surprising. There does exist a need for post-rational morality,
which is essentially a religious dimension of human existence: it is
synonymous with the spiritual life.
The relationship and perfect continuity between the three phases of
morality are brought out in the following passage:
Now you cannot have a harmony of nothings, and rational ethics would
be impossible if pre-rational morality were annulled. And as the
impulse to establish harmony, and the love of order, are themselves
natural and pre-rational passions, so an ulterior shift to
post-rational morality introduces a new natural and pre-rational
passion, the demand for harmony not merely within the human psyche or
within the human world, but between this world and the psyche on the
one hand and the universe, the truth, or God on the other. [10]
One might express this by saying that, although rational ethics adopts a
holistic point of view, post-rational morality does so in an ultimate
sense, by placing both the individual and the natural world in the context
of the transcendent reality postulated by religious systems. But more
important, in my view, is the distinction between rational ethics as a
system of thought and post-rational morality as a way of life--the
spiritual life.
Post-rational morality is borne of despair--despair over the failure of
reason. These systems of morality are "experiments in redemption", [11]
Santayana considers a number of such experiments which have occurred
throughout human history: Epicureanism, Cynicism, Stoicism, Islam,
Platonism, Christianity and Buddhism. Since my concern here is primarily
with the role that Buddhism plays, I will not discuss the other
'experiments in redemption', except to say enough about Christianity to
bring out the contrast with Buddhism. It is after all striking that a
philosopher who was so much a product of Catholic Christian culture should
come to recognise an Eastern religion as a superior expression of the
spiritual life.
There is for Santayana a certain double aspect to Christianity. On the one
hand, the soul of the gospel is really post-rational, which is to say that
it recognises that all earthly things are vanity, and that its effort at
redemption takes the form of renunciation of the world, an emptying of the
will as regards all human desires, thereby realising a deeper peace through
contemplation and mystical detachment. On the other hand, Christianity's
Jewish heritage made this renunciation of the world temporary and partial
only, for it never gave up the pre-rational craving for a delectable
promised land; and although it conceives of a life of the soul in the
beyond, hope of a new order in this world has never been abandoned. Since
the emptying of the will of desire and the renunciation of the world were
half-hearted only, there has been within Christianity a tendency towards a
destructive extreme in its asceticism and its cult of suffering. Buddhism,
being 'a purely negative system', would not allow such extremism: "For a
discipline that is looked upon as merely temporary can contradict nature
more boldly than one intended to take nature's place". [12] And Santayana
elaborates:
The hope of unimaginable benefits to ensue could drive religion to
greater frenzies than it could have fallen into if its object had been
merely to silence the will. Christianity persecuted, tortured, and
burned . . . It kindled wars, and nursed furious hatreds and ambitions
. . . All this would have been impossible if, like Buddhism, it had
looked only to peace and the liberation of souls. Man [in
Christianity], far from being freed from his natural passions, was
plunged into artificial ones quite as violent and much more
disappointing. Buddhism had tried to quiet a sick world with
anesthetics; Christianity sought to purge it with fire. [13]
Buddhism then is for Santayana 'a purely negative system', by which he
means--I believe--that it is a system which through its spiritual
discipline somehow seeks 'to take nature's place'. And this in turn means
that its 'experiment in redemption' takes the form of a practice of
detachment which seeks to silence the will, liberate the soul and bring
about peace. Seeking to 'replace' nature, it does not 'contradict' it,
which is to say that it does not promote violence, hatred and strife among
people, or between body and soul. That Buddhism is an eirenic religion
which seeks to liberate the individual through a practice of detachment is
of course not news to anyone familiar with it. Rather than give a detailed
account of this religious philosophy, what is important for us is to
understand how Santayana conceives of this form of the spiritual life
and--most importantly--what function this highest form of post-rational
morality performs in moral life.
I have said above that Santayana characterises Buddhism as a purely
negative system, and he adds to this that it is wholly pessimistic. He does
not refer explicitly to the Four Noble Truths, but we recognise the
characterisation as an expression of that wisdom, and realise that he does
not speak pejoratively. Since every Buddhistic virtue is said to be viewed
as 'merely removing guilt and alleviating suffering', Santayana also says
that Buddhism is purely remedial; and it is this which has enabled it to
keep morality pure--"free from that admixture of worldly and partisan
precepts with which less pessimistic systems are encumbered". [14]
Elaborating upon the superiority of this system of morality, he continues:
If there is something in a purely remedial system of morality which
seems one-sided and extreme, we must call to mind the far less
excusable one-sidedness of those moralities of prejudice to which we
are accustomed in the Occident--the ethics of irrational
acquisitiveness, irrational faith, and irrational honour. Buddhistic
morality, so reasonable and beautifully persuasive, rising so
willingly to the ideal of sanctity, merits in comparison the
profoundest respect. It is lifted as far above the crudities of
intuitionism as the whisperings of an angel are above a schoolboy's
code. [15]
While it is clear that the superiority of Buddhism lies in its pessimistic
and remedial nature, I believe that this in turn is inseparable from its
epistemological and ontological conception of the world, for it is this
which fosters the practice of detachment from the world which for Santayana
is the essence of the spiritual life. This could ultimately not be
elaborated upon without goring into the complex and central topic of the
practice of meditation; a few words about Santayana's conception of the
spiritual life, and of how this relates to morality, will, however, have to
suffice.
Central to Santayana's philosophy is the distinction between existence and
essence. The realm of existence is the natural world, the dynamic world of
flux, the world of temporal entities which are subject to generation and
corruption. The realm of essence, by contrast, is the realm of eternal and
immutable entities; essences are the forms or aspects that existent objects
may manifest for a time, but many essences are not ever manifested in
existence; the realm of essence is infinite. This basic distinction is
therefore at heart the distinction between the temporal and the eternal;
put in Platonic terms it is the distinction between Becoming and Being, and
in terms of Buddhist philosophy it is the distinction between Samsara and
Nirvana. It is important to realise that, for Santayana, essences--being
eternal--are non-temporal, which is different from saying that they are
everlasting. If there were any everlasting entities, such as the gods and
souls postulated by various religions, they would be temporal, albeit of
infinite temporal extent, and not eternal. Santayana is one with the
Buddhists in believing neither in the existence of gods nor in the reality
of enduring selves.
The following passage makes it clear that Santayana sees a close connection
between his own fundamental ontology and that of
So Nirvana may be called annihilation in that it annihilates
personality, desire and temporal existence; yet the 'Buddha teaches
that all beings are from eternity abiding in Nirvana' so that far from
being nothing Nirvana embraces the whole realm of essence--pure Being
in its infinite implications--from which, of course, existence is
excluded; because since existence is necessarily in flux and is
centred in some arbitrary moment, it itself exists only by exclusion
and with one foot in the grave. [16]
Now the spiritual life, for Santayana, is life in the eternal; which is to
say that, although it is a life which is a possibility for a natural being
in the natural world, it is a life which transcends the natural world to
the greatest possible extent and attends in the fullest possible way to the
realm of essence, to the eternal aspect that temporal things wear. The key
to realising this life in the eternal is detachment, and Santayana makes it
very clear that by this he does not mean indifference. To be detached from
a thing is, spiritually speaking, to regard it with joy; it is to detach it
"from the world that besets and threatens it", and to attach it to the
spirit "to which it is an eternal possession".
But this thing eternally possessed by the spirit is not the thing as
the world knows and prizes it; it is not the person, or nation or
religion as it asserts and flaunts itself, in a mortal anxiety to be
dominant; it is only that thing in its eternal essence, out of which
the stress and the doubt of existence has wholly passed. [17]
This passage points to the fact that the realm of existence can be
distinguished from the realm of essence in less metaphysical terms by
saying that the former is the world of care, anxiety, desire, fear and
passion; whereas the latter is the world freed from these stresses and
doubts. In a sense it is of course misleading to speak of two worlds, for
it is the same world which is experienced in different ways: Samsara and
Nirvana are in a sense the same world and to attain the capacity to sense
the ultimate in the immediate is to be freed from anxiety; it is to realise
the Pyrrhonian ideal of ataraxia, or tranquillity.
The spiritual life entails a complete transformation of the person: in
being liberated from oneself one comes to feel for the first time that
one/s oneself; in being liberated from the world one becomes capable of a
universal love of nature. Santayana elaborates:
Your detachment will not be spiritual unless it is universal; it will
then bring you liberation at once from the world and from yourself.
This will neither destroy your natural gifts and duties nor add to
them; but it will enable you to exercise them without illusion and in
far-seeing harmony with their real function and end. Detachment leaves
you content to be where you are, and what you are . . . yet in your
physical particularity detachment makes you ideally impartial; and in
enlightening your mind it is likely to render your action also more
successful and generous. [18]
In this last remark about the connection between enlightenment and action
we have a clue to the connection between the spiritual life and morality;
for just as the spiritual life transforms the individual, so does it also
transform morality, and it effects what reason can not. A post-rational
morality has value to the extent that it retains some natural impulse and
restores natural morality. It will be recalled that natural, or
pre-rational, morality is the multiplicity of variable and conflicting
natural desires, instincts and impulses; and that rational ethics is an
intellectual attempt to bring order and harmony into natural morality, an
attempt at which it can be at best only partially successful. Post-rational
morality is the subordination of all precepts to some single eventual good.
In the case of Christianity, this is presumably the salvation and eternal
life of the soul in the afterlife; and this rests upon faith in the divine
and redeeming nature of Christ. In the case of Buddhism it is the
Bodhisattva ideal of enlightenment, which involves the overcoming of greed,
hatred and the delusion of an ego isolated from other happenings and
existences; and this realisation of the Buddha nature within ourselves
rests not upon the kind of faith that is central to Christianity, but
rather upon the spiritual discipline of meditation. I hope it has been
clear from my brief account that Santayana's conception of the spiritual
life is close to that ideal.
Although post-rational morality is said to subordinate all precepts to some
single eventual good, it should not be thought that it is Santayana's view
that morality is based on the sort of religious system which constitutes
post-rational morality: morality has an entirely natural genesis, but it
has a wholly ideal or spiritual telos. What remains is to explain how this
spiritual life 'restores' natural morality and why it is that Buddhism is
the superior form of post-rational morality. Speaking generally, Santayana
says that:
Systems of post-rational morality are not original works: they are
versions of natural morality translated into different metaphysical
languages, each of which adds its peculiar flavour, its own genius and
poetry, to the plain sense of the common original. [19]
As an example, he gives the law of Karma, which is the natural experience
of retribution and the fact of character 'ideally extended and made
precise'. In the law of Karma a particular observation about life is raised
to such a level of eminence that we come to imagine it as underlying and
explaining all empirical observations. This 'imaginary extension of the law
of moral continuity and natural retribution' becomes a dogma
which--although it institutes a deeper spiritual law--contains certain
dangers; for it rests on what Santayana calls 'the fantastic metaphysics'
of the transmigration of souls, and--by making my future entirely dependent
on my former conduct--the law tends to deny the fact that the efforts of
others can have a real influence over my salvation through works of love,
pity, science or prayer. In other words, systems of post-rational morality
tend in the direction of faith in the supernatural, which may issue in
destructive superstition, from which even the Buddhistic law of Karma may
not be immune. (Whether Santayana has an adequate understanding of this law
may well be a matter for debate.)
Although some metaphysical dogma or moral fable may be an inescapable
aspect of any post-rational morality, the value of any such system depends
on the extent to which it restores natural morality. It works best when the
symbolism is not deceptive, when the 'supernatural machinery' becomes a
poetic echo of experience which does not offend intelligence. "True sages
and true civilisations can accordingly flourish under a dispensation
nominally supernatural; for that supernaturalism may have become a sincere
form in which imagination clothes a rational and human wisdom" [20].
Although the sophisticated Buddhist would no doubt say that dogma and faith
in supernatural machinery are completely obviated in Buddhism, I believe
Santayana would be inclined to say that in Buddhism they are reduced to
their minimum; in any case, this freedom from dogma is no doubt related to
the negative, pessimistic and purely remedial character of its orientation
discussed above. It is because of its freedom from superstitious dogma that
Buddhism is able to work to redeem us from the illusion which is the
fountain of our troubles: "Ignorance is to be enlightened, passion calmed,
mistaken destiny revoked; only what the innermost being desiderates, only
what can really quiet the longings embodied in any particular will, is to
occupy the redeemed mind." [21] Buddhism was able, he said, to "pierce to
the genuine principles of happiness and misery" [22], and "to combine
universal sympathy with perfect spirituality" [23].
And this perfect spirituality, with the attendant consequences for the
moral life, is ultimately made possible through the spiritual discipline of
meditation--something to which Santayana does not give nearly enough
explicit attention. It is through this practice, and not through dogmas and
doctrines, that the individual realises that detachment which is liberation
both from the world and from the self. The moral power of Buddhism does not
lie in the discipline of the Eightfold Path if this is conceived of as but
one ethical code among others; its power lies in its capacity to transform
natural morality as such through the transformation of the individual as
the result of spiritual practice. This is why Buddhism, more than any other
religious system or post-rational morality, is of universal relevance and
universal appeal, and this is why "It is lifted as far above the crudities
of intuitionism as the whisperings of an angel are above a schoolboy's
code" [24].
NOTES
[1] SANTAYANA, GEORGE (1962) Reason in Science (London, Collier) p. 154.
[2] Reason in Science, pp. 158-159.
[3] Reason in Science, pp. 163, 164.
[4] Reason in Science, p. 171.
[5] Reason in Science, p. 175.
[6] Reason in Science, p. 177.
[7] Reason in Science, p. 188.
[8] Reason in Science, p. 179.
[9] Reason in Science, p. 182.
[10] SANTAYANA, GEORGE (1940) Apologia pro mente sua, in: P. A. SCHLIPP
(Ed.) The Philosophy of George Santayana (hereafter PGS) (New York, Tudor
Publishing) p. 563.
[11] Reason in Science, p. 189.
[12] Reason in Science, p. 201.
[13] Ibid.
[14] Reason in Science, p. 205.
[15] Reason in Science, p. 206.
[16] SANTAYANA, GEORGE (1957) Platonism and the Spiritual Life (hereafter
Platonism) (New York, Harper Torchbooks, p. 30).
[17] Platonism, p. 271.
[18] PGS, p. 571.
[19] Reason in Science, p. 204.
[20] Reason in Science, p. 209.
[21] SANTAYANA, GEORGE (1962) Reason in Religion (London, Collier Books) p.
155.
[22] Reason in Religion, p. 156.
[23] Reason in Religion, p. 155.
[24] Reason in Science, p. 206.
~~~~~~~~
By JOHN MAGNUS MICHELSEN
John Magnus Michelsen, Department of Philosophy, University of Victoria,
Victoria BG, Canada V8W 3PH.
-------------------
欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。
下一篇:The possibility of Oriental influence: in Humes philosophy