2025濠电姷鏁告慨鐑藉极閸涘﹥鍙忛柣鎴f閺嬩線鏌涘☉姗堟敾闁告瑥绻橀弻锝夊箣閿濆棭妫勯梺鍝勵儎缁舵岸寮诲☉妯锋婵鐗婇弫楣冩⒑閸涘﹦鎳冪紒缁橈耿瀵鎮㈤搹鍦紲闂侀潧绻掓慨鐢告倶瀹ュ鈷戠紒瀣健椤庢銇勯敂璇茬仸闁炽儻绠撳畷绋课旀担鍛婄杺闂傚倸鍊搁悧濠勭矙閹达讣缍栫€光偓閳ь剛妲愰幘瀛樺闁告繂瀚ぐ娆撴⒑閹肩偛鍔€闁告粈绀侀弲锝夋⒒娴g瓔鍤欓悗娑掓櫇缁瑩骞掗弴鐔稿櫡闂備浇顕х换鎰瑰璺哄偍濠靛倸鎲$粻鎺撶節閻㈤潧孝闁挎洏鍊濋獮濠冩償閵忋埄娲搁梺璇″灱閻忔梹鎯旈妸銉у€為悷婊勭箞閻擃剟顢楅埀顒勫煘閹达箑鐏崇€规洖娲ら悡鐔兼倵鐟欏嫭绀堥柛鐘崇墵閵嗕礁顫滈埀顒勫箖濞嗗浚鍟呮い鏃堟暜閸嬫捇骞橀瑙f嫽闂佺ǹ鏈悷褔藝閿曞倹鐓欓悹鍥囧懐鐦堥梺璇″枤閸忔ɑ淇婇悿顖fЪ閻庤娲栧鍫曞箞閵娿儺娓婚悹鍥紦婢规洟鏌f惔銏╁晱闁哥姵鐗犻垾锕傛倻閽樺鐎梺褰掑亰閸樿偐娆㈤悙娴嬫斀闁绘ɑ褰冮鎾煕濮橆剚鍤囨慨濠勭帛閹峰懘鎮烽柇锕€娈濈紓鍌欐祰椤曆囧磹濮濆瞼浜辨俊鐐€栭幐楣冨磹閿濆應妲堥柕蹇曞Х椤︽澘顪冮妶鍡樺暗濠殿喚鍏橀弫宥呪堪閸啿鎷虹紓鍌欑劍閿氬┑顕嗙畵閺屾盯骞樼€靛憡鍣伴悗瑙勬礃缁诲牊淇婇崼鏇炲耿婵炲棙鍩堥崯搴g磽娴i缚妾搁柛娆忓暣钘熼柟鎹愭硾婵剟鏌嶈閸撶喖骞冨Δ鈧埢鎾诲垂椤旂晫浜俊鐐€ら崢楣冨礂濮椻偓閻涱噣宕橀纰辨綂闂侀潧鐗嗛幊搴g玻濞戞瑧绡€闁汇垽娼у瓭闁诲孩鍑归崰娑㈠磹閹绢喗鈷掗柛灞捐壘閳ь剟顥撶划鍫熺瑹閳ь剟鐛径鎰櫢闁绘ǹ灏欓鍥⒑缁洖澧茬紒瀣灥椤斿繐鈹戦崶銉ょ盎闂佸搫鍟崐濠氬箺閸岀偞鐓曢柣鏃堟敱閸g晫绱掓潏銊﹀磳鐎规洘甯掗~婵嬵敄閽樺澹曢梺褰掓?缁€浣哄瑜版帗鐓熼柟杈剧到琚氶梺鎼炲€曠€氫即寮婚妶澶婄濞达綀顫夐柨顓㈡⒑閹肩偛濡芥慨濠傜秺婵$敻宕熼姘鳖啋闂佸憡顨堥崑鐔哥婵傚憡鈷戦柟鑲╁仜婵″ジ鏌涙繝鍌涘仴鐎殿喛顕ч埥澶愬閳哄倹娅囬梻浣瑰缁诲倸螞濞戔懞鍥Ψ閳哄倵鎷洪梺鑺ッˇ顖炲汲閻斿吋鐓曢柣妯虹-婢х數鈧鍠栭…宄邦嚕閹绢喗鍋勯柧蹇氼嚃閸熷酣姊绘担铏瑰笡闁告棑绠撳畷婊冾潩閼搁潧浠ч梺鍝勬储閸ㄦ椽鍩涢幋鐘电<閻庯綆鍋掗崕銉╂煕鎼达紕绠插ǎ鍥э躬椤㈡洟鏁愰崶鈺冩澖闁诲孩顔栭崰娑㈩敋瑜旈崺銉﹀緞婵犲孩鍍靛銈嗗姧缁茶姤鍒婃导瀛樷拻濞达絽鎲¢崯鐐烘煙缁嬫寧顥㈤柛鈹惧亾濡炪倖宸婚崑鎾诲础闁秵鐓曟い鎰剁悼缁犮儲绻涢幘鎰佺吋闁哄本娲熷畷鐓庘攽閸パ勭暬闂備胶绮粙鎺斿垝閹捐钃熼柣鏃傚帶缁€鍕煏閸繃顥滄い蹇ユ嫹4闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁绘劦鍓欓崝銈囩磽瀹ュ拑韬€殿喖顭烽幃銏ゅ礂鐏忔牗瀚介梺璇查叄濞佳勭珶婵犲伣锝夘敊閸撗咃紲闂佽鍨庨崘锝嗗瘱闂備胶顢婂▍鏇㈠箲閸ヮ剙鐏抽柡鍐ㄧ墕缁€鍐┿亜韫囧海顦﹀ù婊堢畺閺屻劌鈹戦崱娆忓毈缂備降鍔岄妶鎼佸蓟閻斿吋鍎岄柛婵勫劤琚﹂梻浣告惈閻绱炴笟鈧妴浣割潨閳ь剟骞冨▎鎾崇妞ゆ挾鍣ュΛ褔姊婚崒娆戠獢婵炰匠鍏炬稑鈻庨幋鐐存闂佸湱鍎ら〃鎰礊閺嶃劎绡€闂傚牊渚楅崕鎰版煛閸涱喚鍙€闁哄本绋戦埥澶愬础閻愬樊娼绘俊鐐€戦崕鏌ユ嚌妤e啫鐓橀柟瀵稿仜缁犵娀姊虹粙鍖℃敾妞ゃ劌妫濋獮鍫ュΩ閳哄倸鈧鏌﹀Ο渚Ш闁挎稒鐩铏圭磼濡搫顫庨梺绋跨昂閸婃繂鐣烽幋鐘亾閿濆骸鏋熼柣鎾跺枑娣囧﹪顢涘┑鍡楁優濠电姭鍋撳ù鐘差儐閻撳啰鎲稿⿰鍫濈婵炴垶纰嶉鑺ユ叏濮楀棗澧婚柛銈嗘礋閺岀喓绱掗姀鐘崇亪濡炪値鍋勯幊姗€寮诲澶婄厸濞达絽鎲″▓鏌ユ⒑缂佹ḿ绠栨繛鑼枎椤繒绱掑Ο璇差€撻梺鑺ッ敍宥夊箻缂佹ḿ鍙嗗┑顔斤供閸樿绂嶅⿰鍫熺叆闁哄啫娴傞崵娆撴煛鐎c劌鈧妲愰幒鎾寸秶闁靛⿵瀵屽Λ鍐倵濞堝灝鏋熼柟姝屾珪閹便劑鍩€椤掑嫭鐓冮梺娆惧灠娴滈箖姊鸿ぐ鎺濇缂侇噮鍨抽幑銏犫槈濞嗘劗绉堕梺鍛婃寙閸涘懏鑹鹃埞鎴︽倷閸欏鐝旂紓浣瑰絻濞尖€愁嚕椤愶富鏁婇悘蹇旂墬椤秹姊洪棃娑㈢崪缂佽鲸娲熷畷銏ゆ焼瀹ュ棌鎷洪梺鍛婄箓鐎氼剟寮虫繝鍥ㄧ厱閻庯綆鍋呯亸鎵磼缂佹ḿ娲撮柟宕囧█椤㈡鍩€椤掑嫬鍑犳繛鎴欏灪閻撶喐绻涢幋婵嗚埞婵炲懎绉堕埀顒侇問閸犳洜鍒掑▎鎾扁偓浣肝熷▎鐐梻浣告惈閹冲繒鎹㈤崼婵愭綎婵炲樊浜濋ˉ鍫熺箾閹寸偠澹樻い锝呮惈閳规垿鎮欐0婵嗘疂缂備浇灏▔鏇㈠礆閹烘鏁囬柣鏃堫棑缁愮偞绻濋悽闈浶㈤悗娑掓櫇閳ь剟娼ч惌鍌氼潖濞差亝顥堟繛鎴炶壘椤e搫鈹戦埥鍡椾簼缂佸甯″鏌ュ醇閺囩喓鍔堕悗骞垮劚濡盯宕㈤柆宥嗙厽閹兼惌鍨崇粔鐢告煕閹惧鎳勭紒鍌涘浮閺屽棗顓奸崱娆忓箥婵$偑鍊栧ú鏍涘☉姘К闁逞屽墯缁绘繄鍠婃径宀€锛熼梺绋跨箲閿曘垹鐣峰ú顏呮櫢闁绘ǹ灏欓敍婊冣攽閻樿宸ラ柛鐕佸亞缁煤椤忓應鎷婚梺绋挎湰閻熝囁囬敃鍌涚厵缁炬澘宕禍婊堟偂閵堝鐓忓┑鐐靛亾濞呭懐鐥崜褏甯涚紒缁樼洴楠炲鈻庤箛鏇氭偅闂備胶绮敮鎺楁倶濮樿泛桅闁告洦鍨扮粻鎶芥煕閳╁啨浠﹀瑙勬礃缁绘繈鎮介棃娴舵盯鏌涚€n偅宕屾慨濠冩そ椤㈡鍩€椤掑倻鐭撻柟缁㈠枟閸婂潡鏌涢…鎴濅簴濞存粍绮撻弻鐔煎传閸曨厜銉╂煕韫囨挾鐒搁柡灞剧洴閹垽宕妷銉ョ哗闂備礁鎼惉濂稿窗閺嵮呮殾婵炲棙鎸稿洿闂佺硶鍓濋〃蹇斿閿燂拷26闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁绘劦鍓欓崝銈囩磽瀹ュ拑韬€殿喖顭烽幃銏ゅ礂鐏忔牗瀚介梺璇查叄濞佳勭珶婵犲伣锝夘敊閸撗咃紲闂佽鍨庨崘锝嗗瘱闂備胶顢婂▍鏇㈠箲閸ヮ剙鐏抽柡鍐ㄧ墕缁€鍐┿亜韫囧海顦﹀ù婊堢畺閺屻劌鈹戦崱娆忓毈缂備降鍔岄妶鎼佸蓟閻斿吋鍎岄柛婵勫劤琚﹂梻浣告惈閻绱炴笟鈧妴浣割潨閳ь剟骞冨▎鎾崇妞ゆ挾鍣ュΛ褔姊婚崒娆戠獢婵炰匠鍏炬稑鈻庨幋鐐存闂佸湱鍎ら〃鎰礊閺嶃劎绡€闂傚牊渚楅崕鎰版煛閸涱喚鍙€闁哄本绋戦埥澶愬础閻愬樊娼绘俊鐐€戦崕鏌ユ嚌妤e啫鐓橀柟瀵稿仜缁犵娀姊虹粙鍖℃敾妞ゃ劌妫濋獮鍫ュΩ閳哄倸鈧鏌﹀Ο渚Ш闁挎稒鐩铏圭磼濡搫顫庨梺绋跨昂閸婃繂鐣烽幋鐘亾閿濆骸鏋熼柣鎾跺枑娣囧﹪顢涘┑鍡楁優濠电姭鍋撳ù鐘差儐閻撳啰鎲稿⿰鍫濈婵炴垶纰嶉鑺ユ叏濮楀棗澧婚柛銈嗘礋閺岀喓绱掗姀鐘崇亪濡炪値鍋勯幊姗€寮诲澶婄厸濞达絽鎲″▓鏌ユ⒑缂佹ḿ绠栭柣妤冨Т椤繒绱掑Ο鑲╂嚌闂侀€炲苯澧撮柛鈹惧亾濡炪倖甯掗崐鍛婄濠婂牊鐓犳繛鑼额嚙閻忥繝鏌¢崨顓犲煟妤犵偛绉归、娆撳礈瑜濈槐鍙変繆閻愵亜鈧牕煤閺嶎灛娑樷槈閵忕姷顦繛瀵稿帶閻°劑骞婂鑸电厸鐎广儱娴锋禍鍦喐閻楀牆绗氶柡鍛叀閺屾盯顢曢妶鍛彙婵炲濮弲娑⑩€旈崘顔嘉ч柛鈩兦氶幏鐟扳攽閻愯泛鐨洪柛鐘查叄閿濈偠绠涢幘浣规そ椤㈡棃宕ㄩ婵堟暰闂傚倷娴囬~澶愵敊閺嶎厼绐楁俊銈呮噹缁犵喎鈹戦崒姘暈闁抽攱鍨块弻銈嗘叏閹邦兘鍋撻弴銏犲嚑闁稿瞼鍋為悡鏇㈠箹鏉堝墽绋婚柡鍡╁墯椤ㄣ儵鎮欓幓鎺撴濡炪値鍋呯划鎾诲春閳ь剚銇勯幒鎴濐仼闁哄嫨鍎甸弻銊╂偄閸濆嫅銏㈢磼閳ь剟宕橀埞澶哥盎闂婎偄娲﹂幐濠氭晬閺冨倻纾奸弶鍫涘妿閸欌偓濠殿喖锕︾划顖炲箯閸涘瓨鎯為柣鐔稿椤愬ジ姊绘担钘夊惞闁哥姴妫濆畷褰掓寠婢跺本娈鹃梺纭呮彧缁犳垹绮婚懡銈囩=濞达綀鐤紓姘舵煕濮椻偓娴滆泛顫忓ú顏咁棃婵炴番鍔岀紞濠傜暦閺囥垹绠柦妯侯槹濡差剟姊洪幐搴g畵婵炶尙濞€瀹曟垿骞橀弬銉︾亖闂佸壊鐓堥崰妤呮倶閸繍娓婚柕鍫濋瀵噣鏌¢埀顒佹綇閵娧€鏀虫繝鐢靛Т濞层倗绮婚悷鎳婂綊鏁愰崨顔藉枑闂佸憡蓱閹倸顫忛搹鍦煓闁圭ǹ瀛╅幏閬嶆⒑濞茶寮鹃柛鐘冲哺閹崇偞娼忛妸褜娴勯柣搴秵閸嬧偓闁归绮换娑欐綇閸撗冨煂闂佺娅曢悷銊╁Φ閹版澘绠抽柟瀛樼箘瑜板淇婇悙顏勨偓鏍暜閹烘纾瑰┑鐘崇閸庢绻涢崱妯诲鞍闁绘挻鐟╁鍫曞醇閻斿嘲濮㈤梺浼欓檮缁捇寮婚埄鍐╁缂佸绨遍崑鎾诲锤濡も偓閽冪喖鏌曟繛鐐珕闁稿妫濋弻娑氫沪閸撗€妲堝銈呴獜閹凤拷 闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁绘劦鍓欓崝銈囩磽瀹ュ拑韬€殿喖顭烽幃銏ゅ礂鐏忔牗瀚介梺璇查叄濞佳勭珶婵犲伣锝夘敊閸撗咃紲闂佽鍨庨崘锝嗗瘱闂備胶顢婂▍鏇㈠箲閸ヮ剙鐏抽柡鍐ㄧ墕缁€鍐┿亜韫囧海顦﹀ù婊堢畺閺屻劌鈹戦崱娆忓毈缂備降鍔岄妶鎼佸蓟閻斿吋鍎岄柛婵勫劤琚﹂梻浣告惈閻绱炴笟鈧妴浣割潨閳ь剟骞冨▎鎾崇妞ゆ挾鍣ュΛ褔姊婚崒娆戠獢婵炰匠鍏炬稑鈻庨幋鐐存闂佸湱鍎ら〃鎰礊閺嶃劎绡€闂傚牊渚楅崕鎰版煛閸涱喚鍙€闁哄本绋戦埥澶愬础閻愬樊娼绘俊鐐€戦崕鏌ユ嚌妤e啫鐓橀柟瀵稿仜缁犵娀姊虹粙鍖℃敾妞ゃ劌妫濋獮鍫ュΩ閳哄倸鈧鏌﹀Ο渚Ш闁挎稒鐩铏圭磼濡搫顫庨梺绋跨昂閸婃繂鐣烽幋鐘亾閿濆骸鏋熼柣鎾跺枑娣囧﹪顢涘┑鍡楁優濠电姭鍋撳ù鐘差儐閻撳啰鎲稿⿰鍫濈婵炴垶纰嶉鑺ユ叏濮楀棗澧婚柛銈嗘礋閺岀喓绱掗姀鐘崇亪濡炪値鍋勯幊姗€寮婚敐鍛傜喖鎳¢妶鍛患闂備焦鎮堕崕顖炲礉鎼淬劌鍌ㄩ梺顒€绉甸悡鐔肩叓閸ャ劍绀€濞寸姵绮岄…鑳槺缂侇喗鐟╅獮鍐晸閻欌偓閺佸秵鎱ㄥΟ鍨汗闁哥偟鏁婚弻锝夋偄閸濄儲鍣ч柣搴㈠嚬閸樺墽鍒掗崼銉ョ劦妞ゆ帒瀚埛鎴︽倵閸︻厼顎屾繛鍏煎姍閺屾盯濡搁妷锕€浠撮梺闈涙缁€渚€鍩㈡惔銊ョ闁绘ḿ顣槐鏌ユ⒒娴g瓔娼愰柛搴ゆ珪閺呰埖鎯旈敐鍥╁箵濠德板€曢幊蹇涘煕閹烘嚚褰掓晲閸涱喖鏆堥梺鍝ュ枔閸嬬偤濡甸崟顖f晣闁绘劖鎯屽Λ锕傛倵鐟欏嫭绀冮柨鏇樺灲瀵偊骞囬弶鍨€垮┑鐐叉閼活垱绂嶉悙顒傜鐎瑰壊鍠曠花濂告煕婵犲倻浠涙い銊e劦閹瑩鎳犻鑳闂備礁鎲″鍦枈瀹ュ洦宕叉繛鎴欏灪閸ゆ垶銇勯幒鍡椾壕闂佸疇顕ч悧蹇涘焵椤掑喚娼愭繛鍙夛耿瀹曞綊宕稿Δ鍐ㄧウ濠殿喗銇涢崑鎾绘煙閾忣偆鐭掓俊顐㈠暙閳藉鈻庨幋鏂夸壕妞ゆ挶鍨洪埛鎺懨归敐鍛暈闁哥喓鍋炵换娑氭嫚瑜忛悾鐢碘偓瑙勬礃缁矂鍩ユ径鎰潊闁斥晛鍟悵顐g節閻㈤潧浠﹂柛顭戝灦瀹曠懓煤椤忓嫮鍘遍梺纭呮彧闂勫嫰鎮¢弴鐔虹闁瑰鍊戝鑸靛剳閻庯綆鍋嗙粻楣冩煕椤愩倕鏋戠紒鈧埀顒勬⒑鐎圭媭娼愰柛銊ユ健楠炲啫鈻庨幋鐐茬彴閻熸粍鍨垮畷銉╊敃閿旇В鎷洪柣鐘叉礌閳ь剝娅曢悘鍡涙⒑閸涘⿴娈曞┑鐐诧躬婵″瓨鎷呴崜鍙夊兊闁荤娀缂氬▍锝夊礉閿曗偓椤啴濡堕崱妤€娼戦梺绋款儐閹瑰洭寮婚敐澶嬫櫜闁搞儜鍐ㄧ闁诲氦顫夊ú鏍Χ缁嬫鍤曢柟缁㈠枛鎯熼梺鎸庢婵倝鎮靛⿰鍕瘈闁汇垽娼цⅷ闂佹悶鍔庨崢褔鍩㈤弬搴撴闁靛繆鏅滈弲鐐烘⒑缁洖澧查柕鍥ㄧ洴瀵ǹ顓兼径瀣偓鍫曟煟閹邦喚绀嬮柟鐑橆殔缂佲晛霉閻樺樊鍎愰柣鎾跺枑娣囧﹪顢涘┑鍥朵哗婵炲濮甸惄顖炲蓟閿熺姴骞㈤煫鍥ㄦ⒐閻濇棃姊虹€圭媭娼愰柛銊ユ健閵嗕礁鈻庨幘鏉戞疅闂侀潧顦崕閬嶅绩椤撶喍绻嗛柕鍫濇搐鍟搁梺绋款儐閻╊垶寮崘顔嘉ㄩ柕澶樺枛濞堫偊姊洪崨濠冨闁搞劍澹嗙划璇测槈濞嗗秳绨婚梺鍦劋閸ㄥ灚绂嶉幍顔剧<闂侇剙绉抽幉鐐叏婵犲嫮甯涢柟宄版噽缁數鈧綆鍋嗙粔鐑芥煟鎼淬値娼愭繛鍙夛耿閺佸啴濮€閵堝啠鍋撴担鍓叉僵闁归鐒﹂埢宀勬⒒娴e憡鎯堥悶姘煎亰瀹曟繈骞嬮悙鎵畾闂佸壊鍋呭ú鏍嵁閵忋倖鐓涢柛銉㈡櫅鍟搁梺浼欑秮缁犳牕顫忕紒妯肩懝闁逞屽墮宀h儻顦归柟顔ㄥ洤骞㈡繛鍡楄嫰娴滅偓鎱ㄥΟ鐓庡付闁诲骏濡囬埀顒冾潐濞叉﹢銆冮崨瀛樺仼婵犻潧顑呯粈瀣亜閹烘垵鈧悂鐛崼鐔虹瘈闁汇垽娼ф禒婊勪繆椤愶綆娈橀柟骞垮灲楠炲缍呭鑸靛姇椤懘鏌嶉埡浣告殭鐎殿喗瀵х换婵嬫偨闂堟刀銏ゆ煙閸愯尙绠绘い銏℃閹晠鎮介悽纰夌床闂佸搫顦悧鍕礉瀹€鈧划顓㈠箳濡や焦鍤夐梺鎸庣箓椤︿即鎮¢悩娴嬫斀妞ゆ棁妫勬慨鍥煃瑜滈崜姘洪弽顓ф晪闁挎繂顦粻顕€鏌ら幁鎺戝姉闁归绮换娑欐綇閸撗冨煂闂佺顕滅槐鏇㈠箯瑜版帗鏅搁柣妯虹-閸樻捇鎮楅悷鏉款仾濠㈢懓妫欓弲鍫曟晜闁款垰浜鹃悷娆忓缁€鍐煕閵娿儳浠㈤柣锝囧厴閹垻鍠婃潏銊︽珫婵犵數鍋為崹鍓佹箒濠碘€冲级閸旀牗绌辨繝鍥ㄥ€锋い蹇撳閸嬫捇寮介鐐殿唶闂佺粯鍔﹂崜姘跺矗韫囨搩娓婚悗锝庝邯椤庢銇勯妷锕佸闂囧鏌eΟ鐑樷枙闁稿孩鍔欓弻锝夊箻鐎涙ḿ顦伴梺璇″枟閿曘垽骞冨▎鎾崇闁瑰搫妫欑€垫牠姊绘担鐑樺殌闁哥喎鐏濊灋婵炲棙鎸告闂佸憡娲﹂崹鏉课涘Ο鑽ょ闁糕剝鐟ユ禍楣冩煃鐠囪尙澧︽慨濠冩そ瀹曨偊宕熼浣瑰缂傚倷绀侀鍡涘箲閸ヮ剙鏄ラ柍褜鍓氶妵鍕箳閹搭垰濮涚紓浣割槺閺佸寮诲☉姘e亾閿濆簼绨奸柛锝呯秺閺岋綁鏁愰崨顓熜╅梺浼欑稻缁诲牆鐣烽悢纰辨晢闁稿本鑹剧粻浼存⒒娴g瓔鍤欑紒缁樺浮瀹曟垵鈽夊▎鎰彿婵炲濮撮鍛存偂閳ユ剚鐔嗛柤鎼佹涧婵牓鏌i幘璺烘灈闁哄被鍔岄埞鎴﹀幢濮楀棙锟ョ紓鍌欒兌婵兘宕戦妶澶婅摕婵炴垯鍨归悡姗€鏌熼鍡楀€搁ˉ姘節绾板纾块柛瀣灴瀹曟劙寮介锝嗘闂佸湱鍎ら弻锟犲磻閹炬剚娼╅柣鎾抽椤偅绻濋姀锝庢綈婵炲弶岣块幑銏犫攽閸♀晜鍍靛銈嗘尵婵挳鐛Δ鍛拻濞达絽鎽滅粔娲煕鐎n亷韬€规洑鍗冲浠嬵敇閻愭妲烽梺璇插嚱缂嶅棝宕板Δ鍛亗闁哄洢鍨洪崐鐢告煥濠靛棛鍑圭紒銊ヮ煼閺屽秷顧侀柛鎾寸懃宀e潡鍨鹃幇浣告婵犵數濮甸懝楣冨础閹惰姤鐓熼柡鍐ㄧ墱濡垹绱掗幇顔间槐婵﹨娅i崠鏍即閻愭祴鎷ら梺钘夊暣娴滃爼寮婚敐鍛斀闁搞儯鍔庨ˇ鏉库攽椤旂》榫氭繛鍜冪悼濡叉劙骞掗幊宕囧枔閹风娀宕f径瀣靛敨闂傚倸鍊风粈渚€骞楀⿰鍕弿闁汇垹鎲¢崑瀣煟濡儤鈻曢柛銈嗘礀閳规垿鎮╁畷鍥舵殹闂佸搫鎳忛幃鍌炲蓟閿濆憘鐔煎垂椤旂偓顕楅梻浣呵归敃锕傚磻閵堝拋娼栭柧蹇撳帨閸嬫捇宕烽鐐愶綁鏌曢崱妤€鏆炲ǎ鍥э躬閹瑩寮堕幋鐙€鍎岄梻浣告啞鐢鏁垾宕囨殾濠靛倻枪閸楁娊鏌i弬鍨骇閻庢艾銈稿濠氬磼濞嗘垼绐楅梺绋款儏濡繂鐣烽幋婵冩闁靛繆鈧櫕顓烘俊鐐€栭悧妤冪矙閹烘垟鏋嶉柣妯煎仺娴滄粓鏌¢崘銊モ偓鐟扳枍閺囩姷纾奸柍閿亾闁稿鎹囧缁樼瑹閳ь剟鍩€椤掑倸浠滈柤娲诲灡閺呭爼骞橀鐣屽幐闁诲繒鍋犳慨銈壦夊⿰鍕╀簻闁瑰墽鍋ㄩ崑銏⑩偓瑙勬磸閸旀垿銆佸☉姗嗘僵妞ゆ埈鍋呭ú鏍煘閹达附鏅柛鏇ㄥ亗閺夘參姊虹粙鍖℃敾闁绘绮撳顐︻敊閻e瞼鐦堥梺鎼炲劘閸斿苯鈻撻幋锔解拺闁告挻褰冩禍婵囩箾閸欏澧甸柟顔兼健椤㈡岸鍩€椤掑嫬钃熼柨娑樺濞岊亪鎮归崶銊ョ祷濠殿喗娲熷铏圭磼濡闉嶉梺鑽ゅ暱閺呯姴顕g拠娴嬫闁靛繒濮烽鍝勨攽閻愬弶顥滅紒璇叉瀹曟垿骞樼拠鎻掑敤濡炪倖鍔楅崰搴㈢閻愵剚鍙忔俊顖滃帶娴滈箖鎮楀鐐闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁绘劦鍓欓崝銈囩磽瀹ュ拑韬€殿喖顭烽幃銏ゅ礂鐏忔牗瀚介梺璇查叄濞佳勭珶婵犲伣锝夘敊閸撗咃紲闂佽鍨庨崘锝嗗瘱闂備胶顢婂▍鏇㈠箲閸ヮ剙鐏抽柡鍐ㄧ墕缁€鍐┿亜韫囧海顦﹀ù婊堢畺閺屻劌鈹戦崱娆忓毈缂備降鍔庣划顖炲Φ閸曨垰绠抽悗锝庝簽娴犻箖姊洪棃娑欐悙閻庢矮鍗抽悰顕€宕堕澶嬫櫖濠殿噯绲剧€笛囧箲閸ヮ剙钃熼柣鏂挎憸閻熷綊鏌涢…鎴濇灈妞ゎ剙鐗嗛—鍐Χ鎼粹€茬凹缂備緡鍠楅幐鎼佹偩閻戣棄纭€闁绘劕绉靛Λ鍐春閳ь剚銇勯幒鎴濐伀鐎规挷绀侀埞鎴︽偐閹绘帩浼€缂佹儳褰炵划娆撳蓟濞戞矮娌柟瑙勫姇椤ユ繈姊洪柅鐐茶嫰婢т即鏌熼搹顐e磳闁挎繄鍋涢埞鎴犫偓锝庘偓顓涙櫊閺屽秵娼幏灞藉帯闂佹眹鍊曢幊鎰閹惧瓨濯撮柛鎾村絻閸撳崬顪冮妶鍡楃仸闁荤啿鏅涢悾鐑藉Ψ瑜夐崑鎾绘晲鎼粹剝鐏嶉梺缁樻尰濞叉﹢濡甸崟顖氱疀闂傚牊绋愮花鑲╃磽娴h棄鐓愭慨妯稿妿濡叉劙骞樼拠鑼槰闂佸啿鎼崐濠毸囬弶搴撴斀妞ゆ梻銆嬫Λ姘箾閸滃啰绉鐐茬箻閹晝鎷犻懠鑸垫啺闂備線娼чˇ浠嬪窗閹烘纾婚柟鐐窞閺冨牆宸濇い鏃€鍎抽獮鍫熺節绾版ɑ顫婇柛銊╂涧閻g兘鎮介崨濠傚壒闂佸湱鍎ら弻锟犲磻閹捐埖鍠嗛柛鏇ㄥ墰椤︺劑姊洪幖鐐插婵炵》绻濋幃浼搭敊閸㈠鍠栭幊鏍煛閸愯法搴婂┑鐘殿暯濡插懘宕归幎钘夊偍鐟滄棃鎮伴鈧畷濂稿Ψ閿旇瀚藉┑鐐舵彧缁蹭粙骞夐敓鐘茬畾闁割偆鍠撶粻楣冩倶閻愭彃鈧悂鎮橀懠顑藉亾鐟欏嫭绀冪紒璇插缁傛帡鏁冮崒姘鳖槶閻熸粍绮岀叅闁归棿鐒﹂埛鎴犵磽娴e顏呮叏婢舵劖鐓曢幖瀛樼☉閳ь剚绻堥獮鍐晸閻樺弬銊╂煥閺傚灝鈷旀い鏃€娲熷娲偡闁箑娈堕梺绋款儑閸犳牠鐛繝鍥у窛妞ゆ柨澧介鏇㈡⒑閸︻厾甯涢悽顖滃仱楠炴鎮╃紒妯煎幍婵炴挻鑹鹃悘婵囦繆閻e瞼纾肩紓浣贯缚缁犵偟鈧娲橀敃銏ゅ春閻愭潙绶炴慨婵嗘湰椤庢姊婚崒姘偓宄懊归崶顒夋晪闁哄稁鍘肩粣妤佹叏濡寧纭剧紒鈧崒娑楃箚妞ゆ牗鐟ㄩ鐔兼煕閵堝棙绀嬮柡灞诲€楃划娆戞崉閵娿倗椹抽梻浣呵瑰ù鐑藉窗閺嶎厼钃熼柣鏂垮悑閸婇攱銇勯幒宥堝厡缂佸娲鐑樺濞嗘垹鏆㈡繛瀛樼矤閸撴稑危閹版澘绠婚悹鍥皺閿涙粌鈹戦鏂や緵闁稿繑锕㈠畷鎴﹀箻閹碱厽效闁瑰吋鐣崺鍕磻閵娾晜鈷戦悹鎭掑妼閺嬫柨鈹戦鑺ュ唉婵﹤顭烽、娑樷槈閺嶏妇鐩庨梻浣告惈濞诧箓銆冮崨顔绢洸濡わ絽鍟崐鐢告偡濞嗗繐顏紒鈧埀顒傜磽閸屾氨孝闁挎洏鍊濋幃楣冩煥鐎n剟妾紓浣割儏閻忔繂鐣甸崱娑欌拺缂備焦锚婵鏌℃担瑙勫€愮€殿喗濞婇、鏇㈡晜鐟欙絾瀚藉┑鐐舵彧缂嶁偓濠殿喓鍊楀☉鐢稿醇閺囩喓鍘遍梺缁樓瑰▍鏇犱焊娴煎瓨鐓欏〒姘仢婵倹顨ラ悙杈捐€挎い銏$懇閹虫牠鍩℃繝鍐╂殢闂傚倸鍊峰ù鍥綖婢舵劕纾块柛蹇撳悑閸欏繘鏌曢崼婵愭Ч闁稿鍊块悡顐﹀炊閵娧佲偓鎺楁煕濞嗘劖宕岄柡灞剧洴婵$兘鏁愰崨顓烆潛闂備礁鎲¢弻锝夊磹濡ゅ懏鍎夋い蹇撶墕缁犳氨鎲告惔銊ョ;闁靛鏅滈悡娑㈡倶閻愭彃鈷旈柍钘夘樀閹藉爼鏁愭径瀣幈闂婎偄娲﹂幐鎼佸箖閹寸偞鍙忛柨婵嗘噽婢ф洟鏌嶇憴鍕伌妞ゃ垺鐟у☉闈涚暋閺夋娼紓鍌氬€风欢锟犲闯椤曗偓瀹曠懓鐣烽崶褍鐏婂銈嗘尪閸ㄦ椽宕戦崟顖涚厽闁规崘娅曢幑锝夋煕婵犲嫬浠遍柟顔煎槻楗即宕橀顖ょ秮閹妫冨☉妯诲€梺璇″灡濡啴寮幇鏉跨倞闁冲搫顑囬梻顖涚節閻㈤潧浠╅柟娲讳簽瀵板﹥绂掔€n亞顔愬銈嗗姧缁叉寧鏅堕敓鐘斥拻闁稿本鐟ч崝宥夋煙椤旇偐鍩g€规洘绻勬禒锔剧磼閹惧墎绐楅梻浣芥硶閸犳挻鎱ㄧ€靛摜涓嶉柡宥庣亹瑜版帒绀傞柛蹇曞帶閸撳綊姊烘潪鎵槮闁挎洩绠撻幆鈧い蹇撶墕缁狀垳鈧厜鍋撻柛鏇ㄥ亝閹虫瑩鏌f惔锝呬化闁稿﹥鐗曢—鍐寠婢舵ɑ缍庡┑鐐叉▕娴滄繈鎮炴繝姘厽闁归偊鍨伴拕濂告倵濮橆厽绶叉い顓″劵椤﹀弶銇勯弴銊ュ籍闁糕斁鍋撳銈嗗笂缁讹繝宕箛娑欑厱闁绘ê纾晶鐢告煃閵夘垳鐣甸柟顔界矒閹稿﹥寰勭€n兘鍋撻鍕拺鐟滅増甯掓禍浼存煕濡灝浜规繛鍡愬灲閹瑧绱欓悩鐢电暰婵$偑鍊栭悧妤冨垝鎼达絾鏆滄繛鎴炵懅缁犻箖鏌涘☉鍗炲箻閺佸牆鈹戦纭峰姛缂侇噮鍨堕獮蹇涘川鐎涙ɑ鍎梺鑽ゅ枑婢瑰棝顢曟總鍛娾拻濞达綀顫夐崑鐘绘煕閺冣偓閸ㄩ潧鐜婚懗顖fЬ闂佸憡鐟ラ幊妯侯潖濞差亝顥堟繛鎴炶壘椤e搫鈹戦埥鍡椾簼闁荤啿鏅涢悾鐑芥晲閸垻鏉搁梺鍝勫暙閸婂顢欓弴銏♀拺闁荤喐澹嗛幗鐘绘煟閻旀潙鍔﹂柟顔斤耿椤㈡棃宕奸悢鍝勫笚闂傚倷绀侀悘婵嬵敄閸涘瓨鍊堕悗娑櫳戦崣蹇撯攽閻樻彃鏆為柕鍥ㄧ箖閵囧嫰濮€閳╁啰顦版繝纰樷偓宕囧煟鐎规洏鍔戦、妤呭磼濞戞ḿ顦伴梻鍌氬€搁崐椋庣矆娓氣偓瀹曘儳鈧綆浜跺〒濠氭煕瑜庨〃鍛村垂閸岀偞鈷戞い鎺嗗亾缂佸鎸抽幃鎸庛偅閸愨晝鍘卞銈嗗姧缁茬偓寰勯崟顖涚厸濞达綁娼婚煬顒勬煛鐏炲墽娲存鐐疵灃闁逞屽墴楠炲繘骞嬮悩鎰佹綗闂佽鍎兼慨銈夋偂閻旂厧绠归弶鍫濆⒔绾惧潡鏌i敐搴″籍闁哄本绋掗幆鏃堝Ω閵堝棗鏋ゆ俊銈囧Х閸嬫稓鎹㈠鈧悰顔锯偓锝庝簴閺€浠嬫煙闁箑澧繛鍛躬濮婄粯绗熼埀顒€岣胯钘濇い鎾卞灩绾惧潡鏌熼幆鐗堫棄婵鐓¢弻娑㈠焺閸愵亖濮囬梺缁樻尪閸庤尙鎹㈠┑瀣棃婵炴垶鐟Λ鈥愁渻閵堝啫鍔滅紒顔肩Ч婵$敻宕熼姘祮闂佺粯妫佸▍锝夋偂閸屾粎纾藉ù锝勭矙閸濇椽鎮介婊冧户婵″弶鍔欓獮鎺楀箠瀹曞洤鏋涢柟铏墵閸╋繝宕橀埡鍌ゅ晫濠电姷顣槐鏇㈠磻閹达箑纾归柕鍫濐槸绾惧鏌涘☉鍗炵仭鐎规洘鐓¢弻娑㈩敃閻樻彃濮岄梺閫炲苯鍘哥紒鈧担鐣屼簷闂備礁鎲℃笟妤呭储妤e啯鏅繝濠傜墛閳锋垿姊婚崼鐔恒€掑褎娲熼弻鐔煎礃閼碱剛顔掗悗娈垮枟婵炲﹪宕洪敓鐘插窛妞ゆ棁顫夌€氫粙姊绘担鍛靛綊寮甸鍕殞濡わ絽鍟悞鍨亜閹哄棗浜鹃梺鎼炲灪閻撯€筹耿娓氣偓濮婃椽骞栭悙鎻掑Η闂侀€炲苯澧寸€殿喗鎮傚浠嬵敇閻斿搫骞愰梻浣规偠閸庮垶宕曢柆宥嗗€堕柍鍝勬噺閳锋帡鏌涚仦璇测偓鏇㈡倶閿曞倹鐓涢悘鐐额嚙婵倻鈧鍠楅幐鎶藉箖濞嗗緷鍦偓锝庝簷婢规洟姊洪崨濠勭細闁稿氦娅曠粙澶婎吋閸℃劒绨婚梺鍝勭▉閸嬪嫭绂掗敃鍌涚厽闁规儳宕崝锕傛煛瀹€瀣М鐎殿喗鎸抽幃娆徝圭€n亙澹曢梺闈╁瘜閸樻悂宕戦幘鎰佹僵闁绘劦鍓欓锟�3闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁绘劦鍓欓崝銈囩磽瀹ュ拑韬€殿喖顭烽幃銏ゅ礂鐏忔牗瀚介梺璇查叄濞佳勭珶婵犲伣锝夘敊閸撗咃紲闂佽鍨庨崘锝嗗瘱闂備胶顢婂▍鏇㈠箲閸ヮ剙鐏抽柡鍐ㄧ墕缁€鍐┿亜韫囧海顦﹀ù婊堢畺閺屻劌鈹戦崱娆忓毈缂備降鍔岄妶鎼佸蓟閻斿吋鍎岄柛婵勫劤琚﹂梻浣告惈閻绱炴笟鈧妴浣割潨閳ь剟骞冨▎鎾崇妞ゆ挾鍣ュΛ褔姊婚崒娆戠獢婵炰匠鍏炬稑鈻庨幋鐐存闂佸湱鍎ら〃鎰礊閺嶃劎绡€闂傚牊渚楅崕鎰版煛閸涱喚鍙€闁哄本绋戦埥澶愬础閻愬樊娼绘俊鐐€戦崕鏌ユ嚌妤e啫鐓橀柟瀵稿仜缁犵娀姊虹粙鍖℃敾妞ゃ劌妫濋獮鍫ュΩ閳哄倸鈧鏌﹀Ο渚Ш闁挎稒鐩铏圭磼濡搫顫庨梺绋跨昂閸婃繂鐣烽幋鐘亾閿濆骸鏋熼柣鎾跺枑娣囧﹪顢涘┑鍡楁優濠电姭鍋撳ù鐘差儐閻撳啰鎲稿⿰鍫濈婵炴垶纰嶉鑺ユ叏濮楀棗澧婚柛銈嗘礋閺岀喓绱掗姀鐘崇亪濡炪値鍋勯幊姗€寮诲澶婄厸濞达絽鎲″▓鏌ユ⒑缂佹ḿ绠栨繛鑼枎椤繒绱掑Ο璇差€撻梺鑺ッ敍宥夊箻缂佹ḿ鍙嗗┑顔斤供閸樿绂嶅⿰鍫熺叆闁哄啫娴傞崵娆撴煛鐎c劌鈧妲愰幒鎾寸秶闁靛⿵瀵屽Λ鍐倵濞堝灝鏋熼柟姝屾珪閹便劑鍩€椤掑嫭鐓冮梺娆惧灠娴滈箖姊鸿ぐ鎺濇缂侇噮鍨抽幑銏犫槈濞嗘劗绉堕梺鍛婃寙閸涘懏鑹鹃埞鎴︽倷閸欏鐝旂紓浣瑰絻濞尖€愁嚕椤愶富鏁婇悘蹇旂墬椤秹姊洪棃娑㈢崪缂佽鲸娲熷畷銏ゆ焼瀹ュ棌鎷洪梺鍛婄箓鐎氼剟寮虫繝鍥ㄧ厱閻庯綆鍋呯亸鎵磼缂佹ḿ娲撮柟宕囧█椤㈡鍩€椤掑嫬鍑犳繛鎴欏灪閻撶喐绻涢幋婵嗚埞婵炲懎绉堕埀顒侇問閸犳洜鍒掑▎鎾扁偓浣肝熷▎鐐梻浣告惈閹冲繒鎹㈤崼婵愭綎婵炲樊浜濋ˉ鍫熺箾閹寸偠澹樻い锝呮惈閳规垿鎮欐0婵嗘疂缂備浇灏▔鏇㈠礆閹烘鏁囬柣鏃堫棑缁愮偞绻濋悽闈浶㈤悗娑掓櫇閳ь剟娼ч惌鍌氼潖濞差亝顥堟繛鎴炶壘椤e搫鈹戦埥鍡椾簼缂佸甯″鏌ュ醇閺囩喓鍔堕悗骞垮劚濡盯宕㈤柆宥嗙厽閹兼惌鍨崇粔鐢告煕閹惧鎳勭紒鍌涘浮閺屽棗顓奸崱娆忓箥婵$偑鍊栧ú鏍涘☉姘К闁逞屽墯缁绘繄鍠婃径宀€锛熼梺绋跨箲閿曘垹鐣峰ú顏呮櫢闁绘ǹ灏欓敍婊冣攽閻樿宸ラ柛鐕佸亞缁煤椤忓應鎷婚梺绋挎湰閻熝囁囬敃鍌涚厵缁炬澘宕禍婊堟偂閵堝鐓忓┑鐐靛亾濞呭懐鐥崜褏甯涚紒缁樼洴楠炲鈻庤箛鏇氭偅闂備胶绮敮鎺楁倶濮樿泛桅闁告洦鍨扮粻鎶芥煕閳╁啨浠﹀瑙勬礃缁绘繈鎮介棃娴舵盯鏌涚€n偅宕屾慨濠冩そ椤㈡鍩€椤掑倻鐭撻柟缁㈠枟閸婂潡鏌涢…鎴濅簴濞存粍绮撻弻鐔煎传閸曨厜銉╂煕韫囨挾鐒搁柡灞剧洴閹垽宕妷銉ョ哗闂備礁鎼惉濂稿窗閺嵮呮殾婵炲棙鎸稿洿闂佺硶鍓濋〃蹇斿閿燂拷29闂傚倸鍊搁崐鎼佸磹閹间礁纾归柟闂寸绾惧綊鏌熼梻瀵割槮缁炬儳缍婇弻鐔兼⒒鐎靛壊妲紒鐐劤缂嶅﹪寮婚悢鍏尖拻閻庨潧澹婂Σ顔剧磼閻愵剙鍔ょ紓宥咃躬瀵鎮㈤崗灏栨嫽闁诲酣娼ф竟濠偽i鍓х<闁绘劦鍓欓崝銈囩磽瀹ュ拑韬€殿喖顭烽幃銏ゅ礂鐏忔牗瀚介梺璇查叄濞佳勭珶婵犲伣锝夘敊閸撗咃紲闂佽鍨庨崘锝嗗瘱闂備胶顢婂▍鏇㈠箲閸ヮ剙鐏抽柡鍐ㄧ墕缁€鍐┿亜韫囧海顦﹀ù婊堢畺閺屻劌鈹戦崱娆忓毈缂備降鍔岄妶鎼佸蓟閻斿吋鍎岄柛婵勫劤琚﹂梻浣告惈閻绱炴笟鈧妴浣割潨閳ь剟骞冨▎鎾崇妞ゆ挾鍣ュΛ褔姊婚崒娆戠獢婵炰匠鍏炬稑鈻庨幋鐐存闂佸湱鍎ら〃鎰礊閺嶃劎绡€闂傚牊渚楅崕鎰版煛閸涱喚鍙€闁哄本绋戦埥澶愬础閻愬樊娼绘俊鐐€戦崕鏌ユ嚌妤e啫鐓橀柟瀵稿仜缁犵娀姊虹粙鍖℃敾妞ゃ劌妫濋獮鍫ュΩ閳哄倸鈧鏌﹀Ο渚Ш闁挎稒鐩铏圭磼濡搫顫庨梺绋跨昂閸婃繂鐣烽幋鐘亾閿濆骸鏋熼柣鎾跺枑娣囧﹪顢涘┑鍡楁優濠电姭鍋撳ù鐘差儐閻撳啰鎲稿⿰鍫濈婵炴垶纰嶉鑺ユ叏濮楀棗澧婚柛銈嗘礋閺岀喓绱掗姀鐘崇亪濡炪値鍋勯幊姗€寮诲澶婄厸濞达絽鎲″▓鏌ユ⒑缂佹ḿ绠栭柣妤冨Т椤繒绱掑Ο鑲╂嚌闂侀€炲苯澧撮柛鈹惧亾濡炪倖甯掗崐鍛婄濠婂牊鐓犳繛鑼额嚙閻忥繝鏌¢崨顓犲煟妤犵偛绉归、娆撳礈瑜濈槐鍙変繆閻愵亜鈧牕煤閺嶎灛娑樷槈閵忕姷顦繛瀵稿帶閻°劑骞婂鑸电厸鐎广儱娴锋禍鍦喐閻楀牆绗氶柡鍛叀閺屾盯顢曢妶鍛彙婵炲濮弲娑⑩€旈崘顔嘉ч柛鈩兦氶幏鐟扳攽閻愯泛鐨洪柛鐘查叄閿濈偠绠涢幘浣规そ椤㈡棃宕ㄩ婵堟暰闂傚倷娴囬~澶愵敊閺嶎厼绐楁俊銈呮噹缁犵喎鈹戦崒姘暈闁抽攱鍨块弻銈嗘叏閹邦兘鍋撻弴銏犲嚑闁稿瞼鍋為悡鏇㈠箹鏉堝墽绋婚柡鍡╁墯椤ㄣ儵鎮欓幓鎺撴濡炪値鍋呯划鎾诲春閳ь剚銇勯幒鎴濐仼闁哄嫨鍎甸弻銊╂偄閸濆嫅銏㈢磼閳ь剟宕橀埞澶哥盎闂婎偄娲﹂幐濠氭晬閺冨倻纾奸弶鍫涘妿閸欌偓濠殿喖锕︾划顖炲箯閸涘瓨鎯為柣鐔稿椤愬ジ姊绘担钘夊惞闁哥姴妫濆畷褰掓寠婢跺本娈鹃梺纭呮彧缁犳垹绮婚懡銈囩=濞达綀鐤紓姘舵煕濮椻偓娴滆泛顫忓ú顏咁棃婵炴番鍔岀紞濠傜暦閺囥垹绠柦妯侯槹濡差剟姊洪幐搴g畵婵炶尙濞€瀹曟垿骞橀弬銉︾亖闂佸壊鐓堥崰妤呮倶閸繍娓婚柕鍫濋瀵噣鏌¢埀顒佹綇閵娧€鏀虫繝鐢靛Т濞层倗绮婚悷鎳婂綊鏁愰崨顔藉枑闂佸憡蓱閹倸顫忛搹鍦煓闁圭ǹ瀛╅幏閬嶆⒑濞茶寮鹃柛鐘冲哺閹崇偞娼忛妸褜娴勯柣搴秵閸嬧偓闁归绮换娑欐綇閸撗冨煂闂佺娅曢悷銊╁Φ閹版澘绠抽柟瀛樼箘瑜板淇婇悙顏勨偓鏍暜閹烘纾瑰┑鐘崇閸庢绻涢崱妯诲鞍闁绘挻鐟╁鍫曞醇閻斿嘲濮㈤梺浼欓檮缁捇寮婚埄鍐╁缂佸绨遍崑鎾诲锤濡も偓閽冪喖鏌曟繛鐐珕闁稿妫濋弻娑氫沪閸撗€妲堝銈呴獜閹凤拷
您现在的位置:佛教导航>> 五明研究>> 英文佛教>>正文内容

A Nonreferential View of Language and Conceptual Thought

       

发布时间:2009年04月17日
来源:不详   作者:C. W. Huntington, Jr.
人关注  打印  转发  投稿


•期刊原文

A "Nonreferential" View of Language and Conceptual Thought

in the Work of Tson-kha-pa

By C. W. Huntington, Jr.

Philosophy East and West

V. 33, No.4 (October 1983)

pp. 325-339

Copyright 1983 by the University of Hawaii Press


--------------------------------------------------------------------------------


C. W. Huntington, Jr., is a graduate student in Far Eastern Languages and Literatures, University of Michigan.

p.325

I.GENERAL INTRODUCTION
Ever since the time when Naagaarjuna first set forth the philosophy of the Maadhyamika in his Muulamadhyamakakaarikaa-s scholars have argued among themselves over the meaning of this system and its philosophical implications. The debate began in ancient India, was transported along with the texts into Tibet and China, and now seems to have taken root among academic communities in Europe and America. It is a testament to the profundity of Naagaarjuna's thought that his Maadhyamaka`saastra has not only inspired almost two thousand years of continuing philosophical dialogue, but moreover seems to possess a truly striking reservoir of meaning which lends itself to the most widely disparate attempts at interpretation. Many times it has been victimized as unmitigated nihilism, while more than a few have celebrated it as an extremely subtle and rarefied variety of speculative metaphysics. And yet, within the texts composed by early Indian exponents of the Maadhyamika, most of the force of the dialectic is focused upon the destruction of any and all philosophies of substance ontology or metaphysics, while at the same time these authors very explicitly deny all charges of nihilism. The primary appeal of the linguistic interpretation of the Maadhyamika, which I am about to describe, is simply that it seems to bring us much closer to an understanding of what Maadhyamika philosophers said about themselves, as well as what they had to say about the nature of language and conceptual thought.

With the publication of Chris Gudmunsen's Wittgenstein and Buddhism [1] in 1977, we received the latest and most sophisticated installment in what has now become a rather well-established "linguistic" interpretation of the Maadhyamika. Robinson [2] was among the first to comment on the use of the word "emptiness" as a metalinguistic term intended for the express purpose of describing the primary system of everyday language. Frederick Streng [3] gave considerable impetus to this interpretation, and Douglas Daye [4] developed the notion of language levels into a very convincing analysis of the Maadhyamika's use of language. However, Gudmunsen has presented us with the most comprehensive treatment of this theme to date.

I believe that the essence of Gudmunsen's "Wittgensteinian" approach can be summarized in two points which are intended to describe the nature of the dialectic as a critique of

(a)the correspondence theory of truth, and
(b)the so-called "referential" theory of meaning.

The first of these two theories may be stated as follows: "'A sentence is true if it corresponds to a fact"; [5] and the second, which is taken as a corollary of the first,

p.326

reads: "If a simple expression has meaning then there is a corresponding simple object." [6] The dialectic would then be understood as a critique of these two theories in both a strictly polemical as well as a constructive sense.

1.The polemical function of the dialectic is accomplished through its criticism of the inconsistencies inherent in any kind of metaphysical language, where the expression "metaphysical language" is understood to refer to any sort of linguistic behavior that purports to derive its meaning from a source outside of the sociolinguistic community in which it occurs.

2.The constructive function o f the dialectic is fulfilled through its presentation of a view of language and conceptual thought that is characterized as "nonreferential." This view can itself be rather concisely set forth in the following way, as a reaction to the two theories just mentioned:

(a)The truth value of a collocation of words or concepts derives from its being used in a manner that may be seen as somehow consistent with the conceptual matrix of the sociolinguistic community in which it occurs.
(b)The meaning of a word or concept derives from its usage in some particular socio-linguistic community, and not from its reference to any real object.

A distinct advantage of this interpretation of the Maadhyamika over others that have been proposed is that it allows us to make sense out of the notion of sa.mv.rtisatya, or "conventional truth." If meaning derives exclusively from usage in a conventional, pragmatic, or "social" context, then words and concepts that seem to refer simply to private objects like a dharma or an aatman must be viewed as inherently meaningless. Private objects like these are by definition divorced from any sociolinguistic context, and they are therefore deemed irrelevant for either pragmatic or philosophical purposes. Once they have been disposed of, all that remains are "empty" names, that is, names that have no real object insofar as they do not correspond to any actual objective referent but only to other names. This being the case, Candrakiirti is quite justified in cautioning us against the danger of losing touch with the conventional truth taken for granted by the world. [7]

In the remainder of this paper, I would like to demonstrate just how this nonreferential view of language and conceptual thought can serve as an invaluable aid towards the interpretation of one particular Maadhyamika text composed by the fifteenth century Tibetan scholar Tso^n-kha-pa.

Tso^n-kha-pa was one of the greatest of all expositors of the Maadhyamika, the founder and spiritual inspiration of the Dge-lugs order, and perhaps the most illustrious scholar ever produced by the Tibetan tradition. In what follows I present a translation which is in effect a very short essay extracted from his massive commentary on the Madhyamakaavataara of Candrakiirti, entitled Dbu-ma dgo^ns-pa rab-gsal. [8] This work as a whole is not only the most exhaustive commentary on Candrakiirti's original treatise, but in itself it constitutes a comprehensive and masterly account of Naagaarjuna's system according to the

p.327

interpretation formulated by the Tibetan lineage of Praasa^ngika-maadhyamika. This particular passage well illustrates the clarity and precision that characterize most of Tso^n-kha-pa's writing.

II.THE STRUCTURE OF THE ARGUMENT
It would be misleading to imply that on the basis of this passage we could characterize the Maadhyamika as purely "linguistic " philosophy─I would rather say that in these few pages Tso^n-kha-pa has demonstrated certain very marked features of the Maadhyamika's philosophy of language. This philosophy of language is, however, very clearly placed in the service of Buddhist doctrine, for the essential concern here has been to construct a brief outline of the system of the two truths, by means of an explanation of the concept of selflessness (nairaatmya). In order to accomplish this objective, he unfolds his discussion in two principal phases, both of which are further subdivided into various topics of particular relevance to his argument.

The passage begins with an outline of the mechanism through which all things are said to be posited by conceptual thought. This leads into a discussion of the ontological status of living beings as well as of insentient things which culminates in an assertion to the effect that the person is merely a concept imputed in dependence on a specific collocation of parts (or names), while each of these component parts is itself similarly imputed in dependence on another particular arrangement of composite phenomena. At the close of section A.2, we are told that "neither the composite whole nor the component parts may suitably be posited as the base of such a person, and apart from these two, there is no other entity to act as the base." [9]

In section A.3, a more complex issue is raised and the first direct reference is made to a distinction between empirically real and empirically unreal things according to the following criterion: "Every must fulfill its own function." Causal efficacy is taken as the single criterion of empirical reality in the sense that if the objective referent posited by a word or concept validly performs some function in the context of mundane experience then it is to be granted existential status at the level of conventional truth. In the case of a rope mistakenly apprehended as a snake, the objective referent of our cognition is functionally impotent, and thus we have here one example of something which is empirically unreal. The concept of "self" (aatman) is accordingly split in two: on the one hand, if the "I" is posited as an intrinsically existent subject, then it not only is by definition outside the matrix of cause and effect, but it has in addition already proved under analysis to be a logical impossibility; on the other hand, as a strictly pragmatic device, the concept of "I" as "agent" is in the mainstream of conventional experience and thereby stands the test of empirical reality.

Section A.4 presents a summarization of the first phase of the discussion: "Ultimately even names themselves do not exist, and in the empirical world there

p.328

is nothing aside from that which is posited on the strength of these strictly conventional labels.... Anything whatsoever posited as existent is so posited without searching for the object behind the imputation." And so the question arises: "Apart from these imputed conventional labels, what world either 'exists' or 'does not exist'?"

The problem is set aside for the time being, and the second principal phase of the discussion begins as follows: Granted that all things are merely posited through language and conceptual thought, then it is therefore obvious that any apprehension of an ultimately real object (bhuutaartha) must necessarily be erroneous. In section B. 1, the self to be negated is defined as "an intrinsic nature not posited through the force of conceptual thought"; and this type is further subdivided for the purpose of analysis into two categories of selflessness: the selflessness of living beings (pudgalanairaatmya) and the selflessness of insentient things (dharmanairaatmya).

Generally speaking, sections A.1, 2, and 3 present no particular difficulty, since the argument proceeds clearly from one point to the next and consists for the most part of a series of definitions. The conclusion of the entire argument through A.3 amounts to the assertion that the apprehension of any conceivable (that is, abstract or concrete) objective referent as intrinsically existent must always be made in error, simply because such an apprehension is invariably founded on an entity which is itself actually nothing more than a mental construct imputed through language in dependence on an endless regression of similarly "empty" causes and conditions. This is the emptiness of conventional
truth, or the dependent origination of all conceivable things.

In section A.4, the ramifications of this understanding of conventional truth are developed in detail. Ignorance is defined as a technical term referring to the (mis)apprehension of the meanings of words and concepts as if they referred to entities which were ultimately real. This fundamental error of ontology as it occurs in conjunction with various other intellectual and emotional disorders is identified as the root of sa.msaara, and thereby as the principal cause of all forms of suffering. "With the destruction of ignorance, all the afflictions are destroyed."

"To remove this ignorance, apart from understanding dependent origination as empty, we are instructed in the necessity of understanding the most profound meaning of dependent origination as it becomes manifest [in mundane experience]." Here I believe that we find an answer to the question posed in section A.4.

If mundane experience were judged solely by the criterion of ultimate truth, then "emptiness" would simply mean "nonexistence." When language and conceptual thought do not refer to any real object(s), it would seem as though we are inevitably led to the conclusion that the world does not in fact exist. One may ask at this point--as Tso^n-kha-pa has already done: What world is there apart from names and concepts?

p.329

His answer to this question forms the subject of the final section of this essay, where he asserts that one need not assume either that the objective referent of a concept actually exists or that it does not. In fact, if one thoroughly uproots the notion of a self, then, according to Tso^n-kha-pa, it will become apparent that "selflessness" does not refer to either "existence" or to "nonexistence" in any absolute sense.

III.TRANSLATION FROM THE DBU-MA DGO^NS-PA RAB-GSAL [10]

According to this system, if one understands the mechanism through which all things are merely posited on the strength of conceptual thought, then one will easily recognize that any apprehension of an [intrinsically existent] reality is made in contradiction with this [mechanism]. Here two items must be explained:

A.The mechanism through which all things are posited by conceptual thought; and
B.The apprehension of an [intrinsically existent] reality which is made in contradiction with this [mechanism].

A.All Things Are Merely Posited on the Strength of Conceptual Thought

1.The nature of inanimate things. With respect to the first item, in the Upaalipariprcchaa [11] it is written:

All these various lovely flower blossoms and this beautiful palace of shining gold are without any creator whatsoever, for they have simply been posited on the strength of conceptual thought. The entire world is only imagined through this process of conceptualization.

Here it is said that things are posited on the strength of conceptual thought. In many other [texts] as well we are told that all entities are merely imputations of the conceptualizing process, and that all of them are simply posited through mental constructs. In the Yukti.sa.s.tikaa [12] we find the following passage:

The Buddha has taught that the entire world is occasioned through ignorance, and therefore how can it be improper to say that this world is simply a concept?

The commentary to this passage explains that the phenomenal world is only an imputation of conceptual thought since it does not exist through its own intrinsic nature. Furthermore, it is stated in the Catu.h`sataka: [13]

When concepts do not exist, craving-attachment (raaga) and so forth too are without existence. Therefore, what wise man perceives [the world in terms of] a reified concept (kalpana) and a real object (bhuutaartha)?

The point is further elaborated in the commentary to this passage. [14]

The existence [of craving-attachment] rests upon the conceptualizing process, for when concepts do not exist then it too is deprived of existence. Like an [imaginary] snake imputed on a coiled rope, so without a doubt [craving-attachment] is not established through any intrinsic being.

p.330

In the quotation above, a "real object" would be an object supposed to be established through its own intrinsic being; and a reified concept is [a concept] generated with reference to [such an object]. Having provided an illustration to the effect that attachment and so forth are like the imputation of a snake on a rope, in the commentary it is said that all other things as well are similarly posited by conceptual thought. In the example, the objective referent does not appear clearly and the rope itself is mottled and coiled in the manner of a snake; therefore the thought arises that this is indeed a snake. At that time, neither within the rope as a composite whole nor among its parts is there sufficient cause to assign anything as the base for the distinguishing characteristic of "snake." [15] The snake in the rope is simply an imputation of the conceptualizing process.

2.The nature of sentient creatures. In exactly the same way, the notion of an "I" arises in dependence on the psychophysical constituents (skandha-s). There is insufficient cause to assign anything whatsoever as the base for the distinguishing characteristic of "I" either within the past, present, and future continuum of the group or among the individual constituents. This will be explained in detail later on. The point is that because there is absolutely no cause to apprehend anything as the base of an "I" which would be essence distinct from the individual constituents and the composite group [of the constituents], this "I" is merely posited by conceptual thought, and it does not intrinsically exist. In the Ratnaavalii [16] it is written:

The person is neither earth, nor fire, nor water, nor air, nor space, nor consciousness, nor the composite of them all; and apart from these what person exists?

Here "real person," "living being," "I," and "self" may be considered as synonyms for "person." By "neither earth ... (up to) nor consciousness" is meant "neither any of the parts nor the group of the six elements [associated with] a living being," and this is intended as a refutation of the positing of the collection of elements as a person. The last words [in the quotation] are a refutation of the positing of a person as in essence distinct from the elements.

The person is not accepted in any sense, and this includes the assertion of such a real person in the guise of fundamental mind (aalayavij~naana) and so forth. Here the author of this commentary (that is, Candrakiirti) is in complete accord with the teaching given by the Master (Naagaarjuna). If we understand the mechanism through which conceptual thought [formulates the notion of a] real person, [it will then become apparent that] all other things as well are posited by conceptual thought in a like manner. In the Samaadhiraaja [17] it is said:

This understanding of the apperception of "self" should be applied through wisdom to all things.

And in the Ratnagu.nasa.mcayagaathaa: [18]

One should know all living beings to be exactly like the self, and as is the case with all living beings so it is with every [insentient] thing.

p.331

Finally, the point is clearly made in the Ratnaavalii: [19]

Just as the person is a composite of six elements and consequently is not real; So each of the elements also is a composite and in actuality does not exist.

The meaning of the first line is that the person is imputed in dependence on the six elements. The meaning of the second line is that because nothing can exist without parts and a whole, so each element is also imputed in dependence on the composite of its several parts and therefore does not exist either in actuality or through any intrinsic being.

[The person] is nothing more than an imputation made in dependence on a composite of parts─though neither the composite whole nor the component parts may suitably be posited as the base of such a person, and apart from these two, there is no [other] entity to act as the base.

3.The distinction between empirically real and empirically unreal things: Causal efficacy. Considered from the standpoint of the mechanism through which they are posited by conceptual thought, a water pitcher [and other conventionally real entities] and the imputation of a snake on a rope are similar. However, as regards the [conventional] existence or nonexistence of the two, and their respective potentialities for efficacious behavior, and so forth, they are completely different. Also, with respect to the necessity or lack of necessity involved in formulating the appellations of both, and as to whether or not this process of designation is harmful, and so on, the two of them are absolutely dissimilar.

Every [conventionally real thing] posited by conceptual thought must fulfill its own function. Among those who have composed grammatical and exegetical commentaries, Buddhapaalita, `Santideva, and the present authority (Candrakiirti) are all in agreement that the system of the Master (Naagaarjuna) is extraordinary, and that this matter [of conventional truth based on causal efficacy] is the most profound subtlety of the Maadhyamika view.

4.The emptiness of all things. In connection with this, in the Ratnaavalii [20] we find the following:

Material substances as well as space are nothing more than names, and when the primary elements are non-existent how can there be any concrete form? Even these names do not exist. Feeling, perception, the predispositions, and consciousness are all like the elements; and the self must also be similarly understood, for [in actuality] there is no such self [to be differentiated from] the six primary elements.... (and later) Apart from these imputed conventional labels, what world either "exists" or "does not exist"?

Ultimately, even names themselves do not exist; and at the conventional level there is nothing aside from that which is posited on the strength of these strictly conventional labels. That is to say, [all things] exist only insofar as they are imputed through names. If one thoroughly understands this, then one should also clearly understand that all things necessarily exist in dependence [on one

p.332

another]; that because they are dependently imputed and dependently produced none of them exists through its own intrinsic being; that there is no independent entity not [merely] posited on the strength of some particular conventional label; and that anything whatsoever posited as existent is so posited without searching for the object behind the imputation.

B.The Apprehension of an [Intrinsically Existent] Reality Is Made In Contradiction with the Mechanism Through Which All Things Are Merely Posited by Conceptual Thought

Now for the second item, concerning the apprehension of a being which is not posited merely on the strength of one of the above-mentioned conventional labels.

1.Definition of the type and its two principal divisions. This is the apprehension of existence in reality, as ultimately true, established in actuality, through its own essence, through its own unique distinguishing characteristic, or by virtue of its intrinsic being. The tendency embodied in such as apprehension is innate [to the conceptualizing mind], and the objective referent that is apprehended by it is judged to be real by one extreme of conceptual thought. [21]

[With regard to the Svaatantrika position,] here we must acknowledge the necessity for discriminating between two interpretations of the phrase "ultimate truth," which functions as a specific qualification enjoined upon the object of negation [in certain passages within the suutra-s]. [22] The Svaatantrika maintains that it is not possible for any epistemological object to be established in reality, [as ultimately true, or in actuality]; yet he does assert existence at the conventional level through its own essence, [its own unique distinguishing characteristic, and by virtue of its intrinsic being]. In the interest of those who for the time being simply do not possess the capability to fathom the extremely subtle nature of reality (tattva), [the Svaatantrika position] affords a sophisticated expedient leading to [full comprehension of emptiness].

[The Svaatantrika asserts] an objective referent, acting as the essence of all things, which is itself not dependent on any other conventional concept. By this is meant an intrinsic being not posited through the force of [conceptual thought]─which is just what we refer to as the "self" to be negated. The absence in a living being of any base for the qualification of this self is called "the selflessness of the person"; while the same with respect to the eye, ear, and all other [insentient] things is titled "the selflessness of things." [23] Apprehension of the existence of an intrinsic being within the person and within [insentient] things is spontaneously regarded as the apprehension of two selves. [24] However, the commentary to the Catu.h`sataka [25] states the following:

Here that essence or intrinsic being of any entity which is not dependent on any other [conventional concept] is to be called the "self"; and its absence is the nonexistence of the self. According to the distinction drawn between persons and

p.333

[insentient] things, two [types of selflessness] are recognized: selflessness of phenomena, and selflessness of the person.

And from [the Madhyamakaavataara]: [26]

There are two classifications of selflessness: that of [insentient] things, and that of the person.

In this way, without having created any distinction between the objects of negation as though there were two distinct nonselves, it is suggested that we recognize a [dual] classification according to the thing that acts as the base [for the apprehension of the self]. [27]

2.The innate apprehension of a real self within one's own continuum and within the continuum of other living beings: "I" and "mine." (a)The support: [28] The original text [29] explicitly denies that the psychophysical constituents provide any actual support for the innate view of a real ego-corpus (satkaayad.r.s.ti) [30] occurring as the apprehension of an [ultimately real] self; while in the commentary the support for the [view] is stated to be the self imputed in dependence [on the constituents]. In addition to being the "I" which is the support for the thought of the [personal] "I," [this self] is utilized as the support for [the thought of] the unique person [external to the personal "I"].

(b)The apparent object of cognition: With reference to the apparent object of cognition the auto-commentary states: [31]

On account of the apprehension [of the psychophysical constituents] as "I" (aha.mkaara), one goes on to imagine the existence of a self which does not in fact exist, and then he becomes strongly attached to this self as if it were [ultimately] real.

Thus [the apparent object of cognition] is the [dependently conceptualized] "I" apprehended as established in reality. Elsewhere in the commentary we find the following: [32]

The view of a real ego-corpus is engaged with reference to apparent objects of cognition similar to the thoughts "I" and "mine," and is symptomatic of an afflicted mind.

A cognition which occurs as the thought "I" must naturally arise on the same support as does this innate view of a real ego-corpus. Therefore, that innate apprehension of a self established through its own unique distinguishing characteristic and associated with the person of a continuum other than one's own is certainly an innate apprehension of a real personal self, but it is not [an instance of] the view of a real ego-corpus. [33]

The statement "lodged in apparent objects of cognition similar to the thoughts 'I' and 'mine' " is not an indication that the objective referents which act as the apparent objects of cognition in this manner are simply the apprehensions of the "I" and "mineness" [34]─actually it indicates that the apparent objects of cog-

p.334

nition here are the apprehension of these two as if they existed by virtue of their own unique distinguishing characteristics.

The support of the view of a real ego-corpus occurring as the apprehension of [some entity] as "mine" as "mineness"─this ego-corpus is not [to be understood as] apprehended on the support of one's own eye, and so forth; and the apparent object of cognition founded on this support is the apprehension of "mineness' as existent through its own unique distinguishing characteristic.

In the auto-commentary concerning the line [in the Madhyamakaavataara] which reads "this is mine..." [35] we find the following passage:

The thought "this is mine" can be expressed in conjunction with attachment to apparent objects of cognition [in the form of] any entity other than that which provides the objective referent for the apprehension of [the constituents] as "I." [36]

The following question may arise: Is the apprehension of [some entity] as "mine" here identified as a sort of attachment generated in the thought "this is mine" and founded on the bases of the eye, and so forth? In this connection, the explanation is given that, having first perceived the eye and so forth as "mine," one subsequently develops a strong attachment to this "mine-ness" as if it were [ultimately] real. This is not, however, an indication that the eye and so forth, in acting as bases for the distinguishing characteristic of "mineness," are the support of [the apprehension]: indeed, if this were the case, then there would be no difference between the view of a real ego-corpus and the apprehension of a self within [insentient] things. [37]

3.The innate apprehension of a real self within insentient things. (a)The support: The support of the innate apprehension of a self within [insentient] things is comprised of the physical and psychological constituents of oneself and others, including the eye, ear, nose [and other parts of the body]; as well as all other insentient things not included in the continuum of [a living being].

(b)The apparent object of cognition: This is as previously defined. [38]

4.Ignorance and its reversal. The apprehension of these two selves is the ignorance which binds one to the wheel of sa.msaara. In the `Suunyataasaptati [39] we find the following:

The Master taught that ignorance is the conceptualization of entities which are produced from causes and conditions as ultimately real; and that from [ignorance] arises the twelve-linked [series of dependent origination].

That is to say, the apprehension of "established in actuality" which is founded on entities is ignorance, the root of sa.msaara. Ignorance which is the apprehension of a self within the person is born from the apprehension of a self within [insentient] things. Therefore, it is said: "from ignorance arises the twelve-linked [series of dependent origination]." [40]

The reversal of ignorance is necessarily the realization that what is appre-

p.335

hended through ignorance is [actually] empty and devoid of self. Again, from the `Suunyataasaptati: [41]

With complete realization that when accurately perceived all things are empty, ignorance will no longer arise. This realization is an obstruction to ignorance, and thereby the twelve-linked [series of dependent origination] is brought to a halt.

And from the Dharmadhaatustava: [42]

Concepts of a future life will remain only so long as there is apprehension of "I" or "mine," but if there is accurate perception of the two aspects of selflessness, then the seed of existence will be destroyed.... For a mind completely purified, all things are [seen to be] void of intrinsic being.

In the Catu.h`sataka [43] the following appears:

If the objective referent is seen as devoid of self, then the seed of existence will be destroyed.

And again from the same text: [44]

With the destruction of ignorance all the afflictions are destroyed; and if there is perception of dependent origination, then ignorance will not arise. Therefore, great effort has been expended to explain this particular point.

The ignorance referred to in the above passages is identified as one of the three poisons; it is ignorance associated with the afflictions, because it occurs simultaneously with the apprehension of an "I."

To remove this ignorance, apart from understanding the meaning of dependent origination as emptiness, we are instructed in the necessity of understanding the most profound meaning of dependent origination as it becomes manifest [in mundane experience]. [45] Consequently, the author of this commentary states:

The self is rooted out by the meditator. [46]

We are told that in order to comprehend selflessness, one must thoroughly refute the objective referent of the apprehension of the self. [47] When this particular objective referent is not completely refuted, the mind gravitates there and settles in that place, and such a mind is incapable of gaining access to [realization of] selflessness. The reason for this is that when the mind has perceived any objective referent, [there are only three possible consequences]:

(a)The support is apprehended as a reality;
(b)The support is apprehended as a nonreality; or,
(c)The support is apprehended without making any distinction in terms of the two prior alternatives.

Even if the support is not apprehended as unreal it is not necessary that it be apprehended as real; and likewise, even if there is no perception of the two selves, it is not on this account necessary that there be perception of the absence of the

p.336

two selves--there are any number of cognitions which fall into the third category mentioned above. [48]

Once we have recognized in our own continuum the two apprehensions of a self, we must proceed to establish that the very base of the error (that is, the objective referent) in our own [cognition] does not exist as it is apprehended. If we do not take this step, any attempt at constructing a refutation of the views of others will never get to the point: it is as if we were searching on open marshland for the tracks of a thief who has escaped into the forest. [49] However, if we correctly identify this apprehension of [an intrinsically existent] reality for what it is, then we will understand that a great number of concepts exist which are free from the dual apprehension of a self. In this way, we will be prepared to refute all those who, through their misconceptions, want to deny by means of logical examination into ultimate reality every objective referent apprehended by conceptual thought. [50] 

NOTES
1. C. Gudmunsen, Wittgenstein and Buddhism (New York: Barnes and Noble Books, 1977).

2. Richard Robinson, Early Maadhyamika in India and China (Madison, Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press, 1967).

3. Frederick J. Streng, Emptiness─A Study in Religious Meaning (Nashville, Tennessee: Abingdon Press, 1967).

4. Douglas D. Daye, "Major schools of the Mahaayaana: Maadhyamika," in Buddhism: A Modern Perspective, ed. Charles Prebish (University Park, Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1975), pp. 77-96.

5. Gudmunsen, Wittgenstein and Buddhism, p. 8.

6. Ibid.

7. Madhyamakaavataara of Candrakiirti (kaarika-s and bhaa.sya in the Tibetan trans.), vol. 9,ed.L.de La Vallee Poussin (St. Petersburg: Bibliotheca Buddhica, 1908),VI. 59cd.

8. Tso^n-kha-pa, Dbu-ma dgo^ns-pa rab-gsal (Sarnath, Uttar Pradesh, India:The Pleasure of Elegant Sayings Press, 1973).

9. Concerning the technical term "base"(g`zi, aa`sraya), see below, note 28.

10. The essay translated here constitutes pp. 137-144 of the Dbu-ma dgo^ns-pa rab-gsal, a section from Tso^n-kha-pa's discussion on Madhyamakaavataara, VI. 7.

11. Vinaya-vini`scaya-Upaali-parip.rcchaa, trans. and ed. by Pierre Python (Paris: Adrien-Maisonneuve, 1973), verse 69 and 70a from the Tibetan.

12.Yukti.sa.s.tikaa of Naagaarjuna, ed. in Sanskrit and Tibetan and trans. by S. Yamaguchi in Chuugan Bukkyo Renko (Kyoto, 1944), pp. 31-109 (kaarika 37 and the accompanying commentary).

13. Catu.h`sataka of Aaryadeva, Sanskrit and Tibetan texts with copious extracts from the commentary of Candrakiirti, reconstructed and ed. by Vidhushekhara Bhattacharya (Calcutta: Visva-Bharati Series, no. 2, 1931), VIII. 178 and the accompanying commentary.

14. Ibid.

15. In this instance a legitimate base would have to be an entity that possessed all of the attributes normally predicated to a snake (biting, hissing, etceteras), whereas the snake in the rope is nothing more than a collection of circumstantial evidence which misleads the viewer into believing that he sees something that is in fact not present.

16. Ratnaavalii of Naagaarjuna, T 4158, I. 80. The work has been translated into English by J.

p.337

Hopkins, The Precious Garland and the Song of the Four Mindfulnesses (New York: Harper and Row, 1975).

17. Samaadhiraajasuutra, ed. by P. L. Vaidya (Darbanga, Bihar, India: The Mithila Institute of Post-Graduate Studies and Research in Sanskrit Learning, 1961), XII. 7.

18. As provided by Tso^n-kha-pa, the citation here is simply to Phags-pa sdud-pa, which I interpret as an abbreviated reference to the Ratnagu.nasa.mcayagaathaa; however I have not been able to locate these lines.

19.Op.cit., I.81

20. Op.cit., I.99 and 100; II.114bcd.

21. This is the first of the two "extreme views" (antagraahad.r.s.ti) represented as (1) eternalism (`saasvatad.r.s.ti), and (2) nihilism (ucchedad.r.s.ti) (Confer Abhidharmako`sa, trans. by L. de la Vallee Poussin (Bruxelles, Inst. Belge des Haute Etude Chinoies, 1971), chap. 9, tome V., p. 270).

22. Both the Praasa^ngika-maadhyamika and the Svaatantrika-maadhyamika accept the concept of the two truths as an exegetical device for determining which passages within the suutra-s are definitive (neyaartha), or "ultimately true," and which are to be interpreted (niitaartha) because they do not represent the ultimate truth (paramaartha). The two sects disagree in their understanding of the expression "ultimate truth."

23. According to the Maadhyamika, both types of"self" are causally inefficacious and, therefore, like the snake mistakenly imputed on a rope, they are "real" neither from the ultimate nor the conventional point of view.

24. The technical term "self" (aatman) is used to refer to any concept involving a variety of substance ontology, whether of a sentient "soul" or "spirit," or of an insentient "thing-in-itself." The supposed distinction between these two types of concepts is considered to be trivial by the Maadhyamika: they are both merely instances of "eternalism" (confer note 21). The real objective referent posited by a reified concept is regarded as a reflection of the same innate tendency, whether it appears in sentient or insentient form.

25. I have not located these lines in Candrakiirti's commentary.

26. I have not located these lines either in the Madhyamaka-avataara or in the bhaa.sya.

27. See note 24, above.

28. It would be helpful at this point to clarify the meaning of a few technical terms. "Support" (dmigs-pa; aalambana) and "apparent object of cognition" (rnam-pa; aakaara) are concerned with the cognitive-perceptive event and therefore only with conventional truth. Whereas the particular collocation of elements which underlies a perception is the "support" of that perception, the "apparent object of cognition" is the appearance that this particular arrangement of elements assumes in being perceived under a specific set of conditions. Contrast with these two the terms "base" or "ground" (g^zi;aa`sraya) and "distinguishing characteristic" (mtshan; lak.sa.na). As strictly analytical terms in the metalanguage of philosophy, these words do not refer to the cognitive event, but rather to the conventional objective referent abstracted from our experience of it. The support of every perception is by definition always an empirically real entity, and therefore "base" and "support" refer to the same thing in two different roles. When the apparent object of cognition coincides with the support as it is (that is, as a valid conventional truth), there has occurred an accurate perception (ya^n-dag mtho^n-ba): in such a case a rope is perceived for what it is at the conventional level─a rope (and not a snake). However, as an object of philosophical analysis abstracted from the cognitive event (that is, a "base"), the rope is itself nothing more than a designation made in dependence on a specific conjunction of elements (causes and conditions) which act as its distinguishing characteristics. And apart from its distinguishing characteristics, no base can be found.

29. Madhyamakaavataara, (for example, VI. 142-145).

30. "View of a real ego-corpus" ('jig-thsog-la lta-ba; satkaayad.r.s.ti) is a technical expression specifically denoting the apprehension of a personal self, that is, the apprehension of an "I" as opposed to the apprehension of any other sentient self external to the apprehending subject. The expanded form of the expression reads: 'jig- tshog-la lta-ba 'iri'irtse-mo ~ni-su mtho-ba; and in Sanskrit: vi.m`sati-`sikhaara-samudgataa.h satkaaya-d.r.s.ti-`sailaa.h. Although there is a slight literal discrepancy between the Tibetan gloss and the Sanskrit original, both refer to the "twenty towering peaks of the

p.338

mountain which is the view of a real (abiding) self within transitory, composite phenomena." The twenty aspects of the false view of a self are actually four types of wrong views applied to each of the five psychophysical constituents. These four basic types, as associated with form (ruupa), are as follows: (1) the self is form, like a sovereign; (2) form qualifies the self, like an ornament; (3) form is possessed by the self, like a slave; and (4) form contains the self, like a vessel (confer Mahaavyutpatti, ed. by R. Sakaki (Kyoto: Shingonshu Kyoto Daigaku, 1925, no. 208). Also see: Abhidharmako`sa, V. 7, and L. de La Vallee Poussin's lengthy note on the term in his L'Abhidharmako`sa de Vasubandhu, Tome IV, pp. 15-17).

31. I have not been able to locate these lines.

32. Op. cit., p. 234, line 1.

33. This is simply a matter of definition (see note 24).

34. The concept of "self" which arises in conjunction with the psychophysical constituents is empirically real according to the criteria established in section I.c. It serves as the support, however, for two very different apparent objects of cognition─one which coincides with the strictly functional reality of the "I" and its possessions, and a second which represents these as intrinsically existent entities divorced from language and conceptual thought.

35. Op. cit., I. 3.

36. A person cannot logically consider himself to be in possession of his own innermost self, since this would imply a fracture of the ego into subject and object.

37. The concept of "mineness' is a mere reflex of the concept of "1," and its function is to demarcate the range or define the objects possessed by the "I." Both of these two (that is, "mineness" and "I") are to be distinguished by definition from the concept of a self associated with insentient things.

38. See section B. 2. (b): The apparent object of cognition is the support apprehended as intrinsically existent.

39. `Suunyataasaptatikaarika-naama, T. 3827, verse 64.

40. One begins by attributing existential status to the various things which are posited through language and conceptual thought, and once this is done, he is then forced into constructing a substance ontology in order to account somehow for the nature of this existence. At this point, the only legitimate question has become: Do these things exist in their own right or is existence conferred upon them through the force of another intrinsically existent agent?

41. Op. cit., verse 66.

42. Dharmadhaatustava, T. 1118, verse 64.

43. Catu.h`sataka`saastrakaarika, T. 3846, XIV. 25cd.

44. Ibid., VI. 10cd-ll.

45. That is, one must understand the relationship between the ultimate truth (paramaartha-satya) of emptiness and the conventional truth (sa.mv.rti-satya) of mundane experience.

46. Madhyamakaavataara, VI. 120cd.

47. Any object is "refuted" in this sense by clearly understanding that it exists merely as a designation assigned in dependence on a specific collocation of other similarly "unreal" (that is, nonreferring) designations.

48. It is not necessary to attribute either absolute reality or absolute unreality to the meaning of a word or concept, since any question as to whether or not the objective referent posited by a word or concept is real is an empirical matter to be determined on the basis of its causal efficacy or lack of causal efficacy in the sociolinguistic context (loka-sa.mv.rti) where the word or concept is used.

49. If one argues directly against the concept of "self" then his opponent invariably assumes that such an argument necessarily implies a position entailing the nonexistence of phenomena even at the conventional level, while in fact these two are the very extremes of eternalism and nihilism that seem to epitomize the trap of conceptual thought when it is applied to matters lying outside the range of its authority. The metaphor here is obscure, but I would tentatively propose the following interpretation: "Self" and "nonself" are simply the tracks or absence of tracks on the open marshland which is the meaning of a word or concept, or the objective referent posited by the use of a word or concept.

50. On this, see for example The Garland of Tenets, Praasa^ngika section:

p.339

These days there are those who are immensely proud of their sophisticated views. They say that all objective things are simply erroneous appearances; and thus having perceived [all things] as utterly devoid of existence like the son of a barren woman, these people hold that the most superior practice entails non-attention to anything. They have not so much as caught the scent of the Praasa^ngika. (Le "Grub-mtha rnam-b`zag rin-chen phre^n-ba", ed. with an introd. by Katsumi Mitmaki, in Zinbum: Memoirs of the Research Institute for Humanistic Studies (Kyoto: Kyoto University Press, 1977).

The complete text of the Garland of Tenets has been translated by Hopkins and Sopa in their Practice and Theory of Tibetan Buddhism (London: Rider & Co. Ltd., 1976).








没有相关内容

欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn


            在线投稿

------------------------------ 权 益 申 明 -----------------------------
1.所有在佛教导航转载的第三方来源稿件,均符合国家相关法律/政策、各级佛教主管部门规定以及和谐社会公序良俗,除了注明其来源和原始作者外,佛教导航会高度重视和尊重其原始来源的知识产权和著作权诉求。但是,佛教导航不对其关键事实的真实性负责,读者如有疑问请自行核实。另外,佛教导航对其观点的正确性持有审慎和保留态度,同时欢迎读者对第三方来源稿件的观点正确性提出批评;
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。