APPEARANCE AND REALITY IN CHINESE BUDDHIST
·期刊原文
APPEARANCE AND REALITY IN CHINESE BUDDHIST
METAPHYSICS FROM A EUROPEAN PHILOSOPHICAL
POINT OF VIEW
BONGKIL CHUNG
JOURNAL OF CHINESE PHILOSOPHY
Vol.20 1993
pp.57-72
COPYRIGHT @1993 BY DIALOGUE PUBLISHING COMPANY, HONOLULU,
HAWAII, U.S.A.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
p.57
preliminary Remarks
One of the perennial problems in philosophy turns around the
question of the ideality of the phenomenal world. Arthur
Schopenhauer thought that we are aware of the world only as
mediated through our senses and intellect and hence the world
is idea or representation.(1) William Alston holds that the
really of the world is independent of any sentient being He
says:
Realism is here being understood as the view that
whatever there is [is] what it is regardless of how we
think of it. Even if there were no human beings, whatever
there is other than human thought (and what depends on
that, causally or logically) would still be just what it
actually is."(2)
Anti-realists flatly reject this view. Hilary Putnam holds
the anti-realist view:
[T]he mind makes up the world....Rather,if one must use
metaphorical language,then let the metaphor be this: the
mind and the world jointly make up the mind and the
world....The empirical world...depends upon our criteria
of rational acceptability...we must have criteria of
rational acceptability to even have an empirical
world....I am saying that the 'real world'depends upon
our values.(3)
p.58
Putnam here argues in the conceptual framework of Immanuel
Kant. According to Kant, we perceive something as duck only
through the a priori forms of sensitivity and understanding.
According to Nicholas Wolterstorff, the fundamental issue is
whether there are properties which can both be grasped and
instantiated And if there are, then the suggestion that
concepts [Kant's a priori forms of understanding] are
graspings of properties is obvious.(4) According to Kant and
Putnam, we cannot experience the world as we do unless out
mind constructs it out of whatever is beyond our sensitivity
and understanding. Thus the fundamental issue is whether the
world is the creation of mind as we experience it. Is the
color gold of this watch independent of my perceiving it? The
realist affirms and the anti-realist denies this. This
question cannot be answered unless there is a third agent
which does not use the human perceptual apparatus, and this
is at the moment of no avail. Until such an agent becomes
available, the issue will remain an unsolved philosophical
problem. Modern philosophers starting with Rene Descartes and
George Berkeley have embraced the idealist view with a
variety of minor differences. In China, Hsuan-tsang(a)
(596-664) translated Vasubandhu's (420-500) work on Mere
Ideation (Vijnaptimatrata, Fa-hsiang(b) ) more than a
miliennium before Descartes and Berkeley and one can discern
an unmistakable mark of this idealism in later Hua-yen and
T'ien-t'ai metaphysics.
This study examines the relevance of Chinese Buddhist
metaphysics to the question of appearance and reality.
Through Buddhist discourse is mainly concerned with Buddhist
soteriology - viz., helping sentient beings enter nirvana by
severing their clinging to illusory ego and the phenomenal
world- one can clearly identify some aspects of their
metaphysical views that contribute to the issue under
discussion. Since this study will look at Chinese philosophy
from a European view point, I will first lay out a European
view point from which we can approach Chinese Buddhist views.
I.
1.1. The premises leading to metaphysical idealism are found
in Descartes'
p.59
distinction between the mental and the physical. This
distinction provides the basis for the identification of a
realm of appearances as distinct from reality. For Descartes
the direct objects of perception in the mind are ideas of
three kinds, viz., innate, adventitious, and factitious, all
of which are modifications of the mind. All of these ideas
are caused and some have more reality than others in the
representation of their corresponding reality.(5) In his
proof of the external world, Descartes maintains that God
creates the world and puts impressions of its ideas in our
mind.(6) These ideas do not constitute a reality of public
and physical objects, they can be thought of as a realm of
appearance only. As D.W. Hamlyn points out, idealism stems
from this - with the additional premise that since we do not
have access to anything beyond ideas, the only reality which
we have any justification to assume is that of ideas, of the
appearances themselves.(7) 1.2. Descartes' view that ideas
stand as a veil of perception between us and the world of
reality is more clearly stated by John Locke. According to
Locke, "whatever is so constituted in nature as to he able,
by affecting our senses, to cause by perception in the mind,
doth thereby produce in the understanding a simple idea."(8)
Locke distinguishes ideas in the mind and qualities in the
bodies which cause them: "it will be convenient to
distinguish them as they are ideas or perceptions in our
minds: and as they are modifications of matter in the bodies
that cause such perceptions "(9) For Locke an "Idea" is
whatsoever the mind perceives in itself, in us. or is the
immediate object of perception, thought, or understanding,
and the power to produce any idea in our mind is the quality
of the subject wherein that power is.(10) Locke calls the
solidity, extension,figure,and mobility of any body original
or primary qualities which produce simple ideas in us, viz.,
solidity, extension, figure, motion or rest, and number.
Secondary qualities are such qualities as are nothing in the
objects themselves but are powers to produce various
sensations in us by their primary qualities. Such qualities
as color,slund and taste which we mistakenly attribute to
objects are in truth nothing in the objects themselves,but
powers to produce various sensations in us; and depend on
primary qualities, viz., bulk,figure,texture,and motion of
parts.(11) According to Locke, "the ideas of primary
qualities of bodies are resemblances of them,and their
patterns do really exist in the bodies
p.60
themselves, but the ideas produced in us by the secondary
qualities have no resemblance of them at all. There is
nothing like our ideas, existing in the bodies
themselves."(12) In Locke's view, we cannot imagine that
these simple ideas subsist by themselves, hence we accustom
ourselves to suppose some substratum wherein they do subsist,
and from which they do result, which therefore we call
substance, which is nothing but a supposed but unknown,
support of those qualities we find existing.(13) 1.3. George
Berkeley's idealism replaces the notion of material substance
as the substratum with an infinite spiritual substance. He
says, "... it is infinitely more extravagant to say -- a
thing which is inert operates on the mind, and which is
unperceiving is the cause of our perception."(14) Thus,
Berkeley's idealism is a consequence of Locke's version of
the causal theory of perception. If we can only see our own
ideas caused by the primary and secondary qualities which we
can ex hypothesis never have direct access to, then, argues
Berkeley, it is nonsense to say either our ideas do or do not
resemble the primary or secondary qualities themselves.
Berkeley says that only ideas can resemble another idea; and
"as the supposed originals are in themselves unknown, it is
impossible to know how far our ideas resemble them; or
whether they resemble them at all."(15) Once the notion of
material substance is removed, Berkeley's idealism is the
conclusion to the following argument. All sensible qualities
are nothing but ideas and all physical objects are nothing
but sensible qualities, hence all physical objects are
nothing but ideas. Ideas cannot exist unperceived; an
unperceived idea is therefore self-contradictory. Physical
objects exist unperceived by finite minds.Therefore,they are
perceived by an infinite mind, namely, God.(16) For
Berkeley,mountains,rivers,and stars are all ideas. So,Hegel
pointed out that Berkeley says very little when he says that
things are ideas since this only amounts to recommending a
change of nomenclature and calling things ideas.(17) 1.4. For
David Hume, an unperceived idea is not self-contradictory.
For Hume,perceptions are distinct,independent,self-sufficient
and they occur in bundles as far as we know.The unperceived
perceptions are suggested by two features of our
impressions, constancy and coherence. When I notice
interruptions in my impressions of a mountain,I resolve the
contradiction by supposing unperceived perceptions filling
the gaps
p.61
in the series. Consistency of the mountain despite my
interrupted perceptions of it proves the mountain a bundle of
ideas which continues unperceived. Changing objects are
believed to exist independently if the impressions of them
display coherence. If my fire dies down slowly, the room
temperature goes down whether my impressions of it are
interrupted or not. Hume has to hold this view because
"spiritual substance" and "corporeal substance" are both
pieces of meaningless metaphysical jargon."(18) Thus, neither
Locke's material substance nor Berkeley's spiritual substance
is available to rescue unperceived perceptions. 1.5. Kant
agrees with his predecessors in that we are confined to ideas
or representations (Vorstellungen) even if there is in fact a
reality of things-in-themselves beyond them to which
experience can have no access, he says, "we can know objects
only as they oppear to us (to our senses), not as they may be
in themselves."(19) For Kant, the phenomenal world is totally
dependent on the mind:
All our intuition is nothing but the representation of
appear ance; that the things which we intuit are not in
themselves what we intuit them as being, nor their
relations so constituted in themselves as they appear to
us, and that if the subject, or even only the subjective
constitution of the senses in general. be removed, the
whole constitution and all the relations of objects in
space and time, nay space and time themselves, would
vanish. As appearances, they cannot exist in themselves,
but only in us.(20)
Kant's view,however,differs form Berkeley's since he makes a
distinction within experience between what is subjective and
what is objective. Kant thinks that the objective world as we
take it to be is empiricallly real in the sense that it
differs from the products ot the imagination, but it is
transcendentally ideal since it is stil a matter of
representation by comparison with things-in-themselves.(21)
Kant says, "external objects(bodies), however, are mere
appearances,and are therefore nothing but a species of my
representations,the objects of which are something only
through these representations. Aparts from them they are
nothing."(22) He says
p.62
further, "these external things, namely matter, are in all
their configurations and alterations nothing but mere
appearances, that is, representation in us, of the reality of
which we are immediately conscious."(23) 1.6. Francis H.
Bradley (1864-1924) finds contradictory nature in the
phenomenal world."(24) Bradley appeals to the fact that the
perception of secondary qualities, color, taste, sound, etc.
are circumstance-depedent. He then follows Berkeley in
generalizing that primary qualities such as size and shape
are also nothing but ideas.(25) Berkeley concludes that,
besides God, reality consists solely of ideas; Bradley
concludes that experience is not true.(26)
...There is the one undivided life of the Absolute.
Appearance without reality would be impossible, for what
then could appear? And reality without appearance would
be nothing, for there certainly is nothing outside
appearance. But on the other hand Reality (we must repeat
this) is not the sum of things. It is the unity in which
all things, coming together, are transmuted, in which
they changed all alike, though not changed equally.(27)
1.7. Descartes, Locke, Berkeley, and Kant, then, agree on one
point: the phenomenal world as we experience it is dependent
on our mind for its being. What is presupposed in this view
is that the mind is so marvelous and mysterious as to create
the phenomena of the wonderful world. This point is expressed
in Chinese Buddhist metaphysics by the dictum that the world
is the creation of the mind. This view is explored below in
the works of Hsuan-tsang(a)(596-664), Fa-tsang(c)(643-712),
and Hui-ssu(d)(515-577). Just as the Western philosophers we
have considered disagree on the issue of reality while
agreeing broadly on the nature of the phenomenal world as
appearance, Chinese Buddhist metaphysicians have agreed on
the phenomenality of appearance and disagreed on the
relationship between appearance and reality.
p.63
2.1. Hsuan-tsang's Cheng Wei Hsih Lun(e) (Completion of the
Doctrine of Mere Ideation) echos the views of Berkeley, Hume
and Kant.
According to the Mere Ideation theory,(28) the phenomena
of both ego and things of the external world are equally
evolved by consciousness. Though both are within
consciousness, they seem to be manifested in the external
world. Thus, the seeming ego and external things which are
evolved within the consciousness, although they do not exist
in one sense, nevertheless do not have the nature of a real
ego and real objects, despite their seeming appearance as
such.(29) In other words, what we believe to be external
objects are established in accordance with mistaken beliefs,
and do not exist in the same way as does consciousness. Inner
consciousness, however, being the causation on which the
appearance of external objects depends, is not non-existent
in the same way as the external objects."(30)
This view seems to be identical with Berkeley's idealism
since for Berkeley only the infinite mind, God, and ideas are
created thereby The two views differ, however, in that while
mountains and rivers as ideas are real and distinct from the
infinite mind for Berkeley, they are nothing but
consciousnesses themselves for the mere ideation theory. The
mere ideation theory, however, provides an explanation of the
rela- tionship between ideas and the mind in terms of three
evolving agents, namely, the maturing consciousness(f)
,intellection(g) and discrimination(h).
As regards the (external) localization (of mental
representations), what is meant is that the maturing
consciousness, through the 'maturing' influence of
its'universal'seeds evolves the manifestations of the
seeming matter, etc.,of the receptacle-world,that is,the
external major elements and the matter formed upon
them.Although what is evolved by sentient beings in this
way is separate for each, the resulting appearances are
each like the other,so that there is no differentiation
in their (external) localization.The case is like that of
the illuminations cast by many lamps, which though
separate for each,seem to form a common whole."(31)
p.64
Thus, such objects as mountains and rivers are evolved out of
the universal seeds which belong all to Alaya consciousness
in common. Again, this view is identical with Berkeley's
idealism and more coherent than Hume's phenomenalism which,
as we saw, implies such unperceived perceptions as mountains
and dying fire. However, the mere ideation theory denies any
reality to such mountains and fires if they are not mere
ideas evolved out of the storehouse consciousness.
Hume's claim that such notions as spiritual substance and
corporeal substance are meaningless metaphysical jargon, is
echoed by the Mere Ideation theory. According to the theory,
there are three evolving categories of consciousness and
their mental qualities, all of which are capable of evolving
into two seeming aspects: that of the perceiving division and
that of the perceived division.(32) The evolved perceiving
division is termed "discrimination", because it takes the
perceived division as the object of perception. The evolved
perceived division is termed 'what is discriminated', because
it is taken by the perceiving division as the object of
perception. According to this principle, there are no real
ego or material objects aside from what is thus evolved from
consciousness.(33) What is denied is not mental functions,
Hume's bundles, as inseparable from consciousness, but the
'real' things apart from the aspects of consciousness. The
seeming reality of ego and material objects results from the
discriminating aspect of consciousness. In this way
discrimination evolves what seem to be external objects which
consist of a false ego and material objects.(34)
The Mere Ideation theory, however, anticipates Kant's
world view which admits the noumenal world, for it maintains
that the true nature of all things is chen ju(i)
(Bhutatathata) or Jenuine Thusness.Genuine Thusness, the
reality of all,does not evolve or change,remaining under all
conditions, constantly thus in its nature.(35) Genuine
Thusness as the nature of all phenomenal objects is in no way
connected with the specific character of phenomenal
objects.The thing as in itself is separate forever from the
thing for us.Genuine Thusness or noumenon will never be
perfumed by actual life; it has no relation at all with
phenomenon.(36) This is exactly Kant's view concerning the
relation of noumenon and phenomenon when he says that the
concept of causality is true only of
p.65
the phenomenal world.
2.2. Fa-tsang's Chin shih-tzu chang(j) (Essay on the Gold
Lion) provides a clearer analogy to illustrate the relation
between appearance and reality or phenomenon and noumenon. Of
the Gold Lion, the gold metal symbolizes noumenon and the
figure of the lion symbolizes phenomenon. Fa-tsang identifies
the noumenal world with the realm of principles and the
phenomenal world with the realm of things.(37) The point of
the analogy lies in explaining how the phenomenal world
arises out of the noumenal world. Gold is the primary cause
and the artisan the contributing or secondary cause (material
and efficient causes respectively, to use Aristotle's
terminology). For Fa-tsang, all things and events in the
phenomenal world arise only through the combination of such
causes.
Once the relation of phenomenon to noumenon is
illustrated, the Essay explains the nature of the phenomenal
world. Just as the outward aspect of the lion is illusory,
the phenomenal world is devoid of its own reality while the
noumenal world is free from generation and destruction like
the gold in the analogy."(38) Things of the phenomenal world
are all manifestations of illusions or sole imagination like
Descartes' factitious ideas. Fa-tsang explains the three
characters of things:
The fact that, from (the point of view of) the senses,
the lion exists, is called its (character of) sole
imagination. The fact that (from a higher point of view)
the lion only seemingly exists, is called its (character
of) dependency on others. And the fact that the gold (of
which the lion is made) is immutable in its nature, is
called (the character of) ultimate reality.(39)
The implication of this analogy is that the events and things
of the pheonmenal world have illusory being as the result of
causation but lack any inhernt nature of their own.All beings
in the phenomenal world depend on something else for their
existence.Underlying these appearances,however,there is the
immutable noumenon,which is the ultimate reality,the reality
which Descartes calls 'substance' in its primary sense.The
immutability of the noumenon in the Essay is called
'non-generation'.(40)
The generation of the events and things of the phenomenal
world
p.66
is explained in terms of primary and contributing causes. For
Locke ideas of secondary qualities are the mental
representations of the secondary qualities themselves. For
Fa-tsang, matter is the contributing cause of mind, and mind
is the primary cause of matter. Through the combination of
these causes, illusory manifestations are generated. Being
thus generated through causation, they cannot have any nature
of their own.(41) Descartes and Locke on the nature of what
they call 'idea' seem to have been anticipated by Fa-tsang:
Matter is not self-caused, but necessarily remains
dependent on mind. Mind, however, does not derive from
itself, but is likewise dependent on (phenomenal)
causation. Because of this mutual dependency, what is
generated through causation is indeterminate. It is this
fact of indeterminateness that is called
non-generation.(42)
The claim that matter is dependent on mind resembles Locke's
view that secondary qualities such as color, sound, taste and
odor are, being ideas, dependent on mind for their being.
Descartes' adventitious ideas as modes of the spiritual
substance depend on matter in the external world. Ideas last
as long as they are in the mind. There is no experience of
sweetness in the lump of sugar on the table until it is
produced as an idea in the mind. Fa-tsang says, "matter
[dust] is manifestation of mind. But having thus manifested,
it becomes the contributing cause of mind. There must first
be this causation before any 'mental things' (hsin fa(k)) can
arise."(43) Thus, Locke's causal theory of perception seems
to have been anticipated by Fa-tsang.
Mind and matter discussed here still belong to the
phenomenal world in Kant's conceptual scheme if mind and
matter somehow cause each other. As Fung Yu-lan points out,
(44) the central element in Fa-tsang thought is a permanently
immutable 'mind' which is universal of absolute in its scope
and is the basis for all phenomenal manifestations. This
absolute and immutable mind is more like Berkeley's infinite
spirit or God in which all events and things of the
phenomenal world subsist as archetypal ideas and become
ectypal ideas in time. Thus, Fa-tsang
p.67
explains the phenomenal world as arising from the noumenal
world in terms of 'causation by the realm of noumenon (li fa
chieh(p))'. If we take the term 'noumenon' in the Kantian
sense, the philosophical problem of how what is outside of
time and space can be the cause of the phenomenal world which
is within the realm of space and time, the problem remains
unsolved.
The view of Tung-shan. Liang-chieh (807-869) on noumenon
(li(m) and phenomenon (shih(n)) expounded in his work The
Five Ranks (wu-wei(o)) can be of some help. Two concepts in
the fivefold formula cheng(p) and p'ien(q) signify literally
"the straight" and "the bent." They refer to what is
absolute, one, identical, universal, and noumenal set up in
tension with what is relative, manifold, different,
particular, and phenomenal.(45) The relation of the two
realms is explained in the statement that the absolute
becomes manifest in appearance. In this view, however,
absolute and relative phenomenal are regarded as non-dual
because they are correlative. Relative phenomenal is also
called "marvelous being" and absolute "the true emptiness."
The two are then identified by the expressions "the marvelous
being of true emptiness" and "the true emptiness of marvelous
being." These terms express the quintessence of the
enlightened view of reality.(46) Thus, noumenon as true
emptiness is the gold of the gold lion in the sense that gold
is devoid of the form of lion. The phenomenal world as
representation is empty of its own reality and yet it is a
marvelous appearance of the noumenal.
2.3. In the Ta-ch'eng chih-kuan fa-men(47) (Mahayana Method
of Cessation and Contemplation) traditionally attributed to
Hui-ssu (515-577), one finds what may be called the absolute
idealism of Bradley. Just as Bradley believes that appearance
without reality is be impossible, so the T'ien-t'ai school
regards the whole universe as consisting of a single absolute
mind, known as Chen ju(i)(genuine thusness, Bhutatathata) or
Ju-lai chang(s) (Storehouse of the thus come,
Tathagata-garbha) . These two concepts were previously
met(2.1) in our discussion of the mere ideation school. The
T'ien t'ai(t) school demonstrates an unmistakable influence
of idealism. Thus, we read:
p.68
All things depend upon this mind to have their being, and
take mind as their substance. Regarded in themselves,
they are all void and illusory, and their being is not
(real) being. In contrast to these illusory things, it
(mind) is said to be genuine. Furthermore, though really
not existent, they, because of illusory causation, have
the appearance of undergoing generation and destruction.
Yet when these void things undergo generation, mind
itself is not generated nor, when they undergo
destruction, is it destroyed.(48)
Concerning the identity of the reality in all beings in the
phenomenal world, the text continues: "The Buddhas of all the
three ages together with sentient beings, all equally have
this one mind as their substance. All things, both ordinary
and saintly, each have their own differences and diverse
appearances, whereas this genuine mind is devoid of either
diversity or appearance."(49)
The phenomenal world as appearance of reality is
explained in terms of the substance and function of
Tathagata-garbha or "the Storehouse of the Thus Come." The
storehouse in its substance (ti(u)) is everywhere the same,
and in actual fact is undifferentiated. It is devoid of
differentiation. In its functioning (yung(v)), however, it is
diverse, and hence embodies the natures of all things and is
differentiated."(50) The best simile in the Buddhist
literature- as in the Awakening of Faith in Mahayana-
concerning substance and its function is water and waves.(51)
The two cannot be separated from each other. Water is the
substance of waves and waves are appearance of water. In the
T'ien-t'ai school, the ultimate reality of the universe is
taken to be the clear and pure mind, and is thus a version of
absolute idealism: "We known that all things are the product
of mind."(52) Thus, in this school, nothing real exists
outside of mind, and hence all phenomena are manifestations
of that mind.
III.
What can we say to Alston, Putnam, and Wolterstorff? Is the
lump of sugar on the table white, sweet, and hard when no one
sees, tastes or
p.69
feels it? Alston and Worterstorff think so while Putnam does
not. What about color and the sound of my stereo in my room
where there is no one inside? The tape recorder and camcorder
cannot favor the realists view since there is no third agent
to watch and listen to them who does not have a human
perceptual apparatus.
Descartes, Locke, and Kant admit a reality behind the
veil of perception and hold that the phenomenal world from
the epistemological point of view is an idea or mental
representation. Berkeley cannot allow any real existence
outside of God's mind, so he takes the phenomenal world as
reality in the mind of God. These philosophers all provide
premises for Schopenhauer to conclude that the world is
nothing hut the representation of the will.
The Buddhist schools presented above all agree that the
phenomenal world is the production of the mind. There seems
to be no conclusively valid argument or proof for the truth
of this view; Buddhist views seem to be based on intuitive
insight. If we agree, as in the West, that all of the
qualities we ascribe to physical objects are in reality our
own ideas caused by the objects, then, since cause is utterly
different from effect (ideas) and since we can ex hypothesis
never directly perceive the cause (reality) . then the
Buddhist mere ideation theory can he identified with the
subjective idealism of Berkeley's version, for one admits God
who can be independent of any phenomenal world he creates and
the other Chen hui (genuine thusness) as ultimate reality
which is independent of the appearance of mind as the
phenomenal world.
Fa-tsang and Hui-ssu, both influenced by the philosophy
of mere ideation regard the phenomenal world as the
manifestation of mind. Just as deluded beings can only see
waves without seeing water, deluded beings do not see the
phenomenal world as the manifestation of mind. Here, I
suspect that the notion of Chen ju(Bhuttathata) and
Storehouse of the Thus Come (Tathagata-garbha) are Buddhist
resurrections of the Vedic Brahman as S. Sharma contends.(53)
Brahmanism is, of course, absolute idealism.
Surprisingly enough, then, we can say that the problem of
appearance and reality has troubled philosophers of the East
and the West. I remain unsure whether Putnam or Alston is
right. I have only an intuition
p.70
that my phenomenal world is the representation of my
sentience caused by the external world. My mind is like a
flash light in the night, without which things cannot appear
with all their qualities.
NOTES
1. Die Welt as Wille und Vorstellung, translated as The
World as Will and Representation by E.F.J Payne, 2 vols
(Indian Hills, Colo.,1958).
2. William Alston,"Yes, Virgina. There is a Real World,"
Paul K. Moser ed., Reality In Focus (Englewood Cliffs,
N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1990), p.18.
3. Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History (Cambridge:
Cambridge University press, 1981), pp.134-135.
4. Nicholas Wolterstorff, "Realism vs. Anti-Realism," in
Moser, Reality in Focus, p.62.
5. Rene Descartes,"Meditations on First Philosophy," in
Ralph M. Eaton ed. Descartes (New York: Charles
Scribner's Sons, 1955), Meditation III.
6. Ibid., Meditation V.
7. D.W. Hamlyn, Metaphysics (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1984), pp.15-16.
8. John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding,
Comp., Collated, & Annotated by Alexander Campbell Fraser
(New York: Dover Publishing Co., 1957), Bk.II Ch.VIII, (Vol.One), p.166.
9. Ibid., p.168 [Locke's emphasis]
10. Ibid., p.169
11. Ibid., p.173
12. Ibid., p.173
13. Ibid., Ch.XIII, pp.390-392
14. Ibid., p.198
15. George Berkeley, "Three Dialogues between Hylas and
Philonous, " in David M. Armstrong ed. Berkeley's
Philosophical Writings (London: Collier-Macmillan Ltd.,
1965), p.208.
16. Ibid., pp.174-175.
17. H.B. Acton,"Idealism," in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
8 vols. ed. Paul Edwards (New York: Macmillan, 1967), IV,
p.115. Acton refers to Hegel's Lectures on the History of
Philosophy.
18. David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ed. Selby-Bigge
(Oxford, 1896), p.71
Bk.1, Pt. iv; Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed.
C.W. Hendel (New York, 1958), Sec.XII.
19. Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics,
trans, L.W.Beck (New York, 1951), Sec.10.
20. Immanuel Kant, Kritik der Reinen Vernunft (Hamburg: Felix
Miener Verlag, 1956), Seite, 83. Quoted from Norman Kemp
Smith trans, Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (New
York: St. Martin's Press, 1968), p.82.
21. Ibid., pp.346-347.
22. Ibid., p.346.
23. Ibid., 437.
24. F.S. Bradley, Appearance and Reality (Oxford: The
Clarendon Press, 1893, 1968), Chapters I & II.
25. Ibid., pp.10-12.
26. Ibid., Chapter IV.
27. Ibid., p.432.
28. Taisho shinshu taizokyo(w) [hereafter "I"] (Tokyo: Taisho
lun]. 31:1b. I owe this study to Fung Yu-lan's Chung-kuo
ssu-hsiang hsih(x) and Derk Bodde's English translation
of the work: A History of Chinese Philosophy Vol.II
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1953).
29. Ibid.
30. Ibid.
31. I 1585.31:10a. Fung, History, pp.307-308.
32. I 1585.31:38c.
33. Loc cit.
34. Loc cit.
35. I 1585.31:48a.
36. I 1585.31:48a.
37. I 1875 (Hua-yen yi-hai pai-men(y)).45:627b.
38. I 1880 (Chin shih-tsu chang yun-chien
lui-chiai(z)).45:663c-664a.
39. I 1880.45:664a. Derk Bodde's translation.
40. I 1880.45;664a.
41. I 1875.45:627b-c.
42. I 1875.45:727b-c. Bodde's translation.
43. Ibid.
44. Fung Yu-lan, Chung-kuo ssu-hsiang hsih, p.749; Bodde's
trans., History of Chinese Philosophy, p.359.
45. Heinrich Dumoulin, Zen Buddhism: A History, trans., J.W.
Heisig and P. Knitter (New York: Macmillan, 1988), p.225.
46. Ibid.
47. I 1924.46:641-664.
48. I 1924.46:642b. Bodde's translation.,p.72
49. Ibid.
50. Ibid., 648a.
51. I 1664 (Ta-ch'eng ch'i-hsin lun(aa)).32:576c.
52. Ibid., 650b.
53. See his A Critical Survey of Indian Philosophy (Delhi:
Motilal Banarsidass, 1960), pp.121-123.
CHINESE GLOSSARY
a ¥È®N p ¥¿
b ªk¬Û q ½s ³\
c ªkÂà r ¤j¼¤îÆ[ ªkªù
d ¼z«ä s ¦p¨ÓÂÃ
e ¦¨°ßÃÑ½× t ¤Ñ¥x
f ²§¼ôÃÑ u Åé
g «ä¶q v ¥Î
h ¤l§O w ¤j¥¿·sפjÂøg
i ¯u¦p x ¤¤°ê«ä·Q¥v
j ª÷·à¤l³¹ y µØÄY¸q¸Ñ¦Êªù
k ¤ßªk z ª÷·à¤l¶³¶¡Ãþ¸Ñ
l ²zªk¬É aa ¤j¼°_«H½×
m ²z
n ¨Æ
o ¤¦ì
欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。