Are convenient fictions harmful to your health?
·期刊原文
Are convenient fictions harmful to your health?
Garner, Richard
Philosophy East & West
Vol. 43 No.1
Jan. 1993
Pp.87-106
Copyright by
.
1. Introduction
In the Republic, Socrates observes that the rulers of the
of the medicine of deception for the good of their subjects.
This willingness to prescribe wholesale duplicity has been
shared by distinguished leaders and teachers from many other
times and cultures. Then there are some Buddhists who see the
doctrines of karma, reincarnation, heavens, and hells as
merely expedient devices the use of which is justified by the
results, and this policy is defended in the Lotus Sutra. A
third expedient device is employed by those who appeal to
intrinsic values and binding moral obligations but do not
accept the objectivist implications of the moral language
they use and teach. John Mackie, after arguing that there are
no objective moral obligations or intrinsic values, invites
us to consider what sort of morality we need to "invent," and
Simon Blackburn has recently defended "quasi-realism/' the
view that while there are no objective moral properties, we
should speak as if there are. He says that without a belief
in objective morality, people might do terrible things.
In this essay, I will concentrate neither on lying as such,
nor on the larger topic of deception, but rather on the
deliberate and widespread promulgation of false beliefs by
those who know that they are false.[1] We have, without a
doubt, been served countless convenient fictions by both
cynical and well-meaning deceivers, but what is special about
Plato, the Buddhist authors of the Lotus Sutra, and
"projectivists" like Mackie and
explicit about the need to employ their preferred convenient
fictions.
After setting out the three different convenient fictions, I
will comment on their plausibility, the motives of those who
use them, and the results we might expect from their
widespread acceptance. I will argue that, however much the
defenders of these and similar deceptions might promise, each
of the three is harmful in its own way. I will then look
briefly at some ways of thinking that discourage the use of
such devices, and conclude with some remarks about convenient
fictions today.
2. Plato's Lie
In the course of his discussion of censorship in the
Republic, Plato says that "to be deceived about the truth of
things and so to be in ignorance and error and to harbour
untruth in the soul is a thing no one would consent to."
"Falsehood in that quarter," he adds, "is abhorred above
everything."[2] But our indisputable aversion to falsehood
does not lead Plato to impose a total ban on lies. In
considering whether a god would "tell a falsehood or act one
by deluding us with an apparition," he makes a distinction
between what he calls "real or true falsehood" and "spoken
falsehood." True falsehood is ignorance, or falsehood "in the
soul," concerning reality--that is, false belief. It is a
thing "all gods and men abominate." Spoken falsehood, he
concedes, perhaps ignoring the connection between the two, is
sometimes helpful--"in war, for instance, or as a sort of
medicine to avert some fit of folly or madness that might
make a friend attempt some mischief."[3]
Though spoken falsehood is useful, Plato places a high enough
value on truthfulness to insist that if anyone is to employ
the medicine of the lie, "either on the country's enemies or
on its citizens, it must be the Rulers of the commonwealth,
acting for its benefit."[4] For example, when it comes to
marriage and childbearing, the Rulers are called upon to
"administer a large dose of that medicine we spoke of
earlier."[5] Plato has Socrates prescribe a mating festival
with a lottery rigged to guarantee that "there should be as
many unions of the best of both sexes, and as few of the
inferior, as possible." Only the Rulers are to know of this
ruse; "otherwise," he says, "our herd of Guardians [the
Auxiliaries] may become rebellious."[6]
Socrates notes that while both true and fictitious stories
are to be used in education, "we shall begin our education
with the fictitious kind."[7] Other deceptive practices occur
in the testing of young Guardians, and wherever the Rulers
felt that circumstances necessitated their use, but
notoriously in the best known of Plato's convenient fictions,
the "noble lie," as it is sometimes called. It isn't clear
who is supposed to be telling the lie, but it is clear that
as many of the citizens of the state as possible, even the
Rulers, are to believe it:
I shall try to convince, first the Rulers and the
soldiers, and then the whole community, that all that
nurture and education which we gave them was only
something they seemed to experience as it were in a
dream. In reality they were the whole time down inside
the earth, being moulded and fostered while their arms
and all their equipment were being fashioned also; and at
last, when they were complete, the earth sent them up
from her womb into the light of day. So now they must
think of the land they dwell in as a mother and nurse,
whom they must take thought for and defend against any
attack, and of their fellow citizens as brothers born of
the same soil.[8]
This story is so preposterous that it is hard to see how
anyone might be led to believe it. Plato is well known for
his frequent use of irony, and if he had not been so definite
about the usefulness of falsehoods, we might be tempted to
think he is making fun of paternalistic prevaricators. But
Socrates was not indulging in irony when he recommended "the
medicine of deception"; he was looking for a way to give
citizens a sense of unity, and Guardians a reason to care for
the common people as if they were their brothers. No story
would be likely to have these results if the citizens and
Guardians were not "convinced" of its truth.
We have recently come to understand that we are all children
of one mother, earth, made of the same material, doomed to
the same fate. No imperatives follow from this, but the
realization (and I do not mean mere assent to the
proposition) can change one's approach to life and the world.
It is important to see, however, that what is involved here
is not a false belief; it is a new gestalt, perfectly
compatible with the facts of birth as we know them. Can we
say, then, that, in speaking of the land as a mother and a
nurse, Socrates was only trying to produce some such new
gestalt? Probably not, and certainly the better-known part of
the fable, the famous "myth of the metals," will utterly fail
to achieve the purpose for which it was created (which
involves getting the citizens to accept serious inequalities)
if people do not believe that it describes genuine
differences among kinds of people.
The citizens who emerge from the earth, Plato continues, are
to be told that they were fashioned "by a god" who
mixed gold in the composition of those among you who are
fit to rule, so that they are of the most precious
quality; and he put silver in the Auxiliaries, and iron
and brass in the farmers and craftsmen?
Cornford doesn't use the expression "noble lie" to translate
the Greek term used to characterize this story. The word
'lie' suggests propaganda, so Cornford's Socrates calls the
story "a bold flight of invention." In a footnote, he says
that the story is a harmless allegory and compares it to a
New Testament parable? But the differences between this
"invention" and a standard parable should be obvious. It
doesn't matter if a parable is accepted as the truth about
what happened--the moral is the message. We have missed the
point if we argue that there is no evidence that any
Samaritan did the sood deed related in the Bible. The parable
was told as a way of urging us to exert ourselves to aid
others; it is no more than an illustration and a reminder.
Plato's Myth of the Metals, on the other hand, is a
"caste-fixing" myth--one designed to reconcile citizens to
the division of labor (and of privilege) found in the state.
It offers a bizarre but objectivist account of why some
people deserve to rule--they are made of the right stuff. No
mere parable or metaphor will convince anyone to accept the
authority of a class of aristocrats, so the gold had better
embody, or at least symbolize, some native attribute that
qualifies those who have it to rule and to hold the lives of
others in their hands.
Plato's myth is similar in function to the Vedic Purusa myth,
according to which the Purusa, a giant body, underwent a
primal segmentation. "The brahmin was his mouth, his two arms
were made the rajanya (warrior), his two thighs the vaisya
(trader and agriculturalist) , from his feet the sudra
(servile class) was born."[11] According to both stories,
class divisions are grounded in the way things are. If there
is no gold in the aristocrats, if brahmins and sudras are
made of exactly the same stuff, then unless some other
rationalization can be produced, class distinctions are
arbitrary, conventional, and open-to revision.
Perhaps we should be alerted by the contrast between Plato's
explicit statements about the danger of falsity in the soul
and his willingness to lie to everyone about the most
fundamental matters of reality, birth, religion, and human
nature. His goal was to design a stable society, but he never
seriously considered the dangers facing a society of
profoundly deceived and misguided citizens. We will seriously
consider those dangers in Section 5, but first I want to
introduce two further fictions, and two attempts to defend
the practice of exploiting them.
3. Buddha's Expedient Devices
Mahayana Buddhists have a concept called expedient devices
(upaya). The idea covers everything from skillful teaching to
the promulgating of false beliefs. The Mahayana ideal, the
bodhisattva, is a powerful being who has vowed to save all
sentient beings, and who is wise enough to realize that you
can't save beings without getting their attention, and that
you can't get their attention unless you offer them something
they want.
It is also a Mahayana tradition that when understanding is
reached, the Buddhist doctrine itself will be discarded, as
is a raft that has taken us where we wanted to go. This
suggests that many, or even all, the major Buddhist concepts
are "expedient devices," designed to help people get to where
they can grasp the real message (emptiness, perhaps, or
dependent origination). Included among these obsolescent
devices are the distinction between samsara and nirvana, the
concepts of karma and reincarnation, and the many heavens and
hells Buddhists were fond of describing.[12]
In the Lotus Sutra, the Buddha is said to have tailored his
teaching to his audiences:
The Buddha, by the power of expedient devices,
Demonstrates the teaching of the three vehicles. The
living beings, attached to this object and that, He
attracts and thus enables to extricate themselves.[13]
The "three vehicles" in question are the way of the
bodhisattva (seeking the salvation of both the self and
others), the pratyekabuddha (seeking one's own salvation by
one's own efforts), and the sravaka (aiming at the salvation
of one's own self by "listening to a Buddha and taking his
sermons to heart."[14] The sutra explains that this was a
teaching for a former time, when people were not yet ready
for the truth, or the "one teaching," which is that everyone
is capable of reaching the highest level of enlightenment,
Buddhahood, in this life. The Lotus Sutra does not say that
the Buddha actually lied to people about this, but if he said
things designed to give people a mistaken impression, then
some deception was involved, was it not? If, on the other
hand, he simply encouraged different people to seek different
paths, depending on their abilities, there need have been no
lies and no deception.
In chapter three of the Lotus Sutra a parable is offered to
support the practice of using expedient devices. The parable,
told by the Buddha to his disciple Sariputra, is about a
wealthy lord who has placed his children in a huge but
run-down house that catches fire. The children are occupied
with their toys, to which, we are told, they are addicted.
When the father cries to them about the fire, they pay no
attention, so busy are they with their play. Finally the
desperate father hits upon the expedient of telling them that
just those toys they most love are outside the door waiting
for them. This they hear and understand, and immediately
scamper to their safety.
Now the father has, strictly speaking, told the children a
lie; but few would blame him for that. In any case, it is one
he could make up for by getting his children the toys he
mentioned. But, as the Buddha tells this story, the father
appears to have compounded his mendacity. He would have been
ashamed, in his great wealth, to give his children what he
actually promised, so, instead, he gives them toys of much
greater value. The Buddha asks: "Is the man guilty of
falsehood or not? Sariputra answers that he is guilty of no
falsehood, that even if he gave them nothing at all, "he
would still be no liar."[15]
Perhaps Sariputra is confusing usefulness with truthfulness,
because on any plausible account of lying I can think of, the
father was guilty of falsehood. He produced a false statement
intending for his children to believe it. He said there were
toys when in fact there were no toys. If that isn't a lie or
a falsehood, what is?
It makes more sense to admit that the father did lie to his
children, and then to say that his lie was completely
justified. Then we can point out to Sariputra that the
question is not whether the father is a liar (one lie does
not a liar make), but whether the father lied. He did.[16]
Later in the sutra, when the Buddha is explaining this
parable, he insists that he is, like the father, "free of
falsehood," in spite of the fact that he "first preached the
three vehicles in order to entice the beings, then conveyed
them to deliverance by resort to only the One Great Vehicle."
As we have seen, the Buddha may have been free of falsehood,
but that depends on what he actually said when he preached
the three vehicles.
The point of the parable, of course, is that what the Buddha
offered (identified in the Lotus Sutra as "Buddhahood") would
not have been attractive to people at every level of
development. So, just as with the children, it is expedient
to promise less than one gives. We are like the children in
the burning house: without stories of heaven and hell, karma
and reincarnation, without the best devices bodhisattvas can
devise to help us, we will never escape from the flames of
our desires to set out on the road that leads to what is
really valuable.
The Buddhist idea of convenient devices, unlike Plato's noble
lie, has actually been put into use; people have been taught
according to their abilities and Buddhists have been
shamelessly eclectic in the devices they have been willing to
employ and the stories they have been willing to tell.
However much good this might have done, it still makes sense
to ask, as we did of Plato's proposed deception, whether we
might be harmed by accepting these myths and stories as
truths. After considering one more expedient device, we will
turn to this question.
4. The Projectivist's Moral Practices
Now I want to introduce a third convenient fiction, not as
fantastic as the ones favored by Plato and the Buddhists, but
pervasive enough to deserve our attention. Imagine that the
fears of the moral skeptics are justified, and that the
amoralist, who stands to morality as the atheist stands to
religion, is right. We make moral judgments with confidence
and great frequency, but, according to a skeptical tradition
that includes Hume, John Mackie, and Simon Blackburn, those
moral judgments are not related to the world in the way that
our claims about trees and tables are; rather, our "moral
distinctions" originate from within and are "projected" onto
an otherwise value-free world.
Hume said that while reason gives "knowledge of truth and
falsehood," sentiment is the origin of the distinctions of
morality. Reason "discovers objects as they really stand in
nature, without addition or diminution," but sentiment "has a
productive faculty, and gilding or staining all natural
objects with the colours, borrowed from internal sentiment,
raises in a manner a new creation."[17] He illustrates the
point by inviting us to consider a vicious act of "wilful
murder." If you examine it closely, he says, you will find
motives, volitions, and thoughts, but you will not find the
vice till you look within "and find a sentiment of
disapprobation, which arises in you, towards this
action."[18] Vice and virtue, like sounds, heat, and cold,
"are not qualities in objects, but perceptions in the
mind."[19] The error of the moral realist is to assume that
they are, in the words of Mackie, part of the fabric of the
world.
Mackie interpreted Hume's claim about how we gild and stain
objects as an endorsement of "projectivism," and, like Hume,
he embraced this form of antirealism. He held, in opposition
to noncognitivists, that moral judgments have a truth-value,
and, in opposition to moral realists and ethical naturalists,
he claimed that every single one of them is false. Moral
judgments are false because they all involve the mistaken
claim, or assumption, or presupposition that there are
"objectively prescriptive" moral properties or facts,
intrinsic values, or binding categorical imperatives. Like
Hume, Mackie believed that this assumption of moral realism
is embedded in our language. "Ordinary moral judgments," he
said, "include a claim to objectivity, an assumption that
there are objective values."[20]People who use evaluative
language may not comprehend what this assumption involves, or
how peculiar it is, but if Mackie is right, that is what they
assume--and they are wrong every time. That is why Mackie's
antirealism is described as an "error theory."
Now, if we accept Humean projectivism and an error theory, as
Mackie does, we cannot avoid the question of what to do with
our error-infested moral language. Shall we continue to use
it as a convenient fiction, or give it up and look for other
ways to get people to behave?
Mackie chooses to use it, as the subtitle of his book,
Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, and his attempt to
"construct a practical morality" indicate. He says that
morality is needed to counteract self-love and confined
generosity,[21] and he adds that the notion of a right is
"valuable and indeed vital."[22] He knows that talk about
rights and duties is either talk about an institution or talk
within an institution, but does not give much attention to
the fact that "talk within an institution" is often done by
people who are not aware that their words apply only within
that institution.
Perhaps Mackie thinks that he, and those who have grasped the
truth of the error theory, can use moral language in some
purged and non-erroneous way, but this is not so clear. If
moral philosophers use the same words ordinary people do,
they must use them with the same meaning, at least when they
are addressing the general public; if they know there are no
moral properties, then when they say things that imply that
there are moral properties they are saying and implying
things they know to be false.
Simon Blackburn has defended a position regarding the truth
of moral utterances that he calls "quasi-realist
projectivism."[23] As a projectivist, he agrees with Hume and
Mackie that "we have sentiments and other reactions, caused
by natural features of things, and that we 'gild or stain'
the world by describing it as if it contained features
answering to these sentiments."[24] This seems to place him
squarely within the antirealist camp; but, unlike Mackie,
Blackburn insists that we can, without error or falsehood,
speak and operate as if moral realism is true. Quasi-realism,
then, is projectivism without the error theory. explain how
error and falsehood can be avoided in these circumstances. In
Hume's Moral Theory, Mackie observes that
escape error by challenging "the view that a claim to
objectivity is implicit in our ordinary ways of speaking."
Mackie, however, assures us that "direct attention to
traditional ways of thinking about morality... will still
detect such a claim."[25]
This issue about the ordinary use of moral language obviously
cannot be settled here. Perhaps neither
can be conclusively identified as unequivocal advocates of
widespread deception. In that case it would be simple enough
to say that the position we really want to talk about is the
one that combines antirealism, projectivism, and the error
theory, and yet still insists, as
idea that some things are objectively wrong, though a
projection of our feelings, is "something we need to
cultivate to the right degree and in the right place to avoid
the (moral) defect of indifference to things that merit
passion."[26]
5. Three Questions
There are three questions to ask Plato's rulers, Buddhists,
and projectivists who advocate the use of morality as a false
but expedient device: (a) What is the likelihood that the lie
(or deception) will be believed? (b) What is the motive in
telling (or perpetrating) this particular lie (or deception)?
(c) What are the positive and the negative effects of the lie
(or deception) being believed or not believed?
A. Credibility. I think we can agree that Socrates' story
never had a chance. It would not be easy to convince a child
that all of his or her early experiences were only a dream,
and it would be even harder to support the "noble lie," as
Socrates' fellow citizens learned for themselves that
children do not spring from the earth.
The Buddhist devices, on the other hand, do not go counter to
our daily experience; they just occupy a space beyond
experience. No current experience can confirm or disconfirm a
statement about former lives or future punishments, and the
concept of karma offers an explanation for all of life's
mysterious events. Indeed, inequality and both good and bad
fortune can be seen as evidence for the karma theory.
It is hard to believe that our childhood was a misleading
dream, easier to believe in karma and reincarnation, and hard
not to believe in the objectivity of morality. This last
deception (if it can be called that)is not one perpetrated on
a gullible public by some philosopher-king or bodhisattva; it
is one that people perpetrate upon themselves. The only
people who can be charged with duplicity here are those
projectivists who see through the illusion, and then decide
to continue using moral language on the grounds that the rest
of us will be better off if we continue to believe in
objective values and obligations.
B. Motives. What motivated Plato to recommend his fiction
about birth, and all the other deceptions Socrates mentions,
was a mistrust of ordinary people and an inflated opinion of
the ability of the "wise" to make good decisions. Beyond
this, it must also be recorded that Plato and his
aristocratic audiences were interested in promoting a form of
government in which the "best" (among whom they numbered
themselves) were given positions of power.
Buddhists were motivated by compassion more frequently than
by political ambition, and their expedient devices were
introduced to help others avoid suffering and reach
enlightenment. They believed themselves to be in possession
of a teaching that was too deep and demanding for people
scarred by ignorance and bad mental habits, and so they
devised ways to attract adherents and to help beginners
develop focused and tranquil minds. People were told, for
example, that if they would call out the name of a
bodhisattva ceaselessly, then that bodhisattva would help
them calm their minds. It probably never occurred to the
novices that it is impossible to worry about anything when
the mind is busy repeating some series of sounds. Minds were
calmed, so even if the stories of bodhisattvas are only
expedient devices, their use was thought justified by the
results.
Hume argued that justice is one of those "artificial" virtues
that produces "pleasure and approbation by means of an
artifice or contrivance."[27] We invent it to protect
ourselves "from the selfishness and confin'd generosity of
men, along with the scanty provision nature has made for
[our] wants."[28] Mackie agrees with Hume about the "object
of morality," and says that "it is necessary for the
well-being of people in general that they should act to some
extent in ways that they cannot see to be (egoistically)
prudential and also in ways that in fact are not prudential.
Morality has the function of checking what would be the
natural result of prudence alone."[29] Morality, he says, "is
not to be discovered but to be made,"[30] and, at least in
part, remade? But if we remake it by leaving out the
objective prescriptivity, we will have reduced what is left
to something with the force of a request or a suggestion--and
that will be of little use in checking prudence or any other
strong impulse?
Mackie and
error theory. But whether moral claims involve a systematic
error or not, both insist that we are better off with
morality than without it.[33]
us to continue speaking as moral realists do because, as he
says, without a belief in objective values and obligations
people "are more likely to do the most awful things."[34]
We can agree that the Buddhists, those projectivists who want
us to speak (and think) as moral realists, and probably even
Plato, have only the best motives. Nevertheless we also know
that deception and the false beliefs that result can hurt us
even when the intentions of the deceiver are good, so it is
possible, even likely, that widespread acceptance of
substantial false beliefs will have unanticipated bad
results. When we look at deceptive practices from the
"perspective of the liar," as Sissela Bok terms it, we focus
on our own projections of the advantages of the deception,
and ignore potential disadvantages. We also tend to neglect
nonmendacious ways of arriving at the desired result?
C. Results. Because we cannot know the future, it is always
possible to debate the prospective results of some course of
action. We never have certain knowledge of the advantages and
disadvantages of telling some lie, or of participating in
some deceptive behavior or practice. Nevertheless, we are all
reasonably skilled at making predictions, and while some of
our predictions are bound to be mistaken, others have a good
chance of being right, and it would be disastrous to ignore
them.
It would not be rash to predict that a massive fabrication
like the "myth of the metals" would do serious damage if
injected into a person's or a society's cognitive system and
accepted as true. We never believe single, isolated facts;
rather we subscribe to complex, interrelated networks of
mutually supporting beliefs. In order to sustain the belief
that we were formed in the earth like potatoes, we would have
to find some way to neutralize the many facts that don't fit
with that fanciful claim. For every fact denied, a great
number of related facts would have to be deleted and other
supporting falsehoods produced.
If the members of any society should come to believe
Socrates' fable, or any similarly fabricated radical fiction,
the result would be a very confused group of people, unsure
of what to believe, and unable to trust their normal
belief-producing mechanisms. It is not wise to risk having a
society of epistemological wrecks in order to achieve some
projected good through massive deception. Usually the
situation is neither as dire nor as predictable as those who
would save the day with a lie believe. Too often what is
saved is not the day, but the lavish life-styles of those who
have discovered the need to deceive.
Throwing off lies and facing the truth is a sign of
epistemological health, in a community or in an individual.
The self-confidence gained from having seen through a
deception, and initiatives taken in response to the actual
situation, are likely to serve the citizens of a state far
better than any proposed deception would have done.
What now of the Buddhist devices? At least they do not begin,
as Plato's fable did, by asking us to reject what we have
seen and learned about our everyday world. The Buddhists (and
other religious moralists) try to secure improvements in our
behavior and in the quality of our lives by appealing to
alleged facts about former and future lives, about heaven and
hell, and about fantastically powerful beings.
In his introduction to Tsong-ka-pa's Illumination oft he
Thought, itself a commentary on Chandrakirti's Supplement to
the
makes use of an expedient device in his discussion of
compassion. He concludes from three assumptions--infinite
time, a finite number of souls, and reincarnation--that in
some former existence every present enemy was a friend, a
loved one, perhaps even a mother. Consequently, he reasons,
it is appropriate to love everyone as if they were our
closest relative because they are, or at least were in some
former existence?
Before attempting to promote some such story as a convenient
fiction, we should ask if it is really likely to have the
effect predicted. If sincerely believed, the three
assumptions above probably would have some positive
effect--though perhaps not as much as a rational person might
expect. It is also possible that the same improvement might
be achieved by other less speculative means. Surely we do not
have to believe that someone was our mother or our friend in
a past life in order to feel compassion for her or him. If it
should turn out that my only reason for treating people well
is some such false (or at least unstable) belief, what
happens when I abandon that belief?
The Buddhist devices are not necessary for moral reform or
personal growth, though sometimes they are helpful. But if
they are imaginative fabrications, we can ask if they are,
like a belief in Socrates' myth, harmful. Well, they do hold
some potential for harm. Any time we do not see things as
they are, we are to some extent made incapable of appropriate
behavior. Further, if fanciful doctrines are widely believed,
people will become confused about what it takes to have a
true belief, and will be encouraged to indulge in many
spurious modes of cognition. A belief in karma and
reincarnation, or in heaven and hell, may make us feel better
about reality if our current life isn't turning out well; but
by the same token, it may rob us of a chance to practice
courage, and may actually discourage us from improving our
lives by making us believe either that we deserve what we are
getting, or that justice will be achieved in the fullness of
time.
Finally, what of objectivist moral language? If we agree that
intrinsic value and objective moral obligation are
projections of our feelings, and not to be found in the
world, we would be smart to evaluate the effects of beliefs
and practices based on a belief in moral realism.
Moral arguments are widely conceded to be unresolvable, and
moral language to be manifestly unclear, emotively loaded,
and theory-laden. There is every reason to think its
continued use will result in more inconclusive debates, moral
impasses, and stalled reforms. Since even the worst behavior
can be wrapped in moral terms, no atrocity or abuse need lack
superficial moral backing, and if its defenders are clever
and skilled, moral criticism can be held off indefinitely.
Indeed, a belief in objective value has always been called
upon to justify slavery, terrorism, genocide, exploitation,
and other atrocities. As long as morality is seen as
objective, we will be encouraged to hope that we can convince
others to accept what we think we know to be the obvious
moral truth. This keeps the arguments going and the
philosophers in business. It also prevents us from coming to
grips with the potentially irreconcilable character of our
positions and the need for compromise and tolerance.
It is true that if we abandon the habit of speaking as the
moral realist does, we will no longer be able to say that
slavery and cruelty are morally wrong, but how important is
it to be able to say that? What is important is the
elimination of slavery and cruelty; the vapid pronouncement
that they are morally wrong pales when compared to a sincere
and deeply felt aversion to them, and we can have that
without holding false beliefs about moral objectivity.
Just as the belief in reincarnation and supernatural beings
scrambles our epistemology by making us think we have access
to knowledge of an unusual kind, so does the belief in
objective moral truth. If there are no moral truths, then all
the epistemology designed to account for moral knowledge is a
waste of time and a source of confusion. What if we could
drop moral language and the deceptive practices of the
quasi-realist? What if we could just face the truth of
antirealism, acknowledging that morality arises in the way
Hume says, and that there is no intrinsic value, no objective
moral obligation, and no moral or human rights beyond
conventional practice-bound institutional ones? I do not
share
became common knowledge. After all, if moral beliefs are
projections of our feelings, we still have the feelings to
motivate us--so where is the problem?
While belief in the objectivity of morality may not be as
harmful as a belief in Plato's fable, it has its dangers. It
sets us up for interminable debates, and distracts us from
the task of gaining and developing two things necessary for
solving the problem of coexisting with others--knowledge and
compassion. Not only are fables about human history, human
nature, and moral objectivity unnecessary for the generation
of compassion; I would argue that what generates compassion
more quickly than anything else is unadulterated acquaintance
with people as they are, with their feelings, hopes, dreams,
intentions, and fears. If we can manage to stay in touch with
that, and successfully encourage others to do the same, we
can forget about Platonic lies, former lives, and myths of
intrinsic value and objective duty. Informed compassion is a
better, more faithful, and more reliable check on egoism than
morality or deceit could ever hope to be.
6. Whom Can You Trust?
We have no way of knowing what was really believed by those
who taught what even others of their time saw as false
doctrines. Perhaps many more of the claims of the ancient
sages were deliberate deceptions than we think. If so, the
ancient sages would not have been likely to tell us--a fact
that might lead us to wonder if we can trust anyone who
claims to be teaching some important truth that we cannot
readily verify for ourselves.
If we think of ourselves as in a position to institute or
support some convenient fiction, we can see that there are
(at least) three circumstances in which we would be inclined
not to do so. (1) We might have a positive reason to avoid
them. Perhaps we think they do more harm than good, or we
have (as a condition of being given membership or power)
agreed to avoid their use. (2) We could just be empty of any
desire to influence the behavior of others, in which case we
would be neither motivated nor inclined to exploit convenient
fictions. (3) Finally, we might have amassed so much power
over others that we have no need to bother with deception.
These three possibilities can be illustrated by the Jains,
the Daoists, and the Legalists.
A. The Jains. Jains have always been given high marks for
truthfulness, and, at the same time, they embrace one of
the most elaborately described nonempirical cosmologies in
the universe,[37] one that might strike someone outside
the Jain tradition as an obvious fabrication. What should
we believe about what they believe?
In The Jaina Path of Purification, Padmanabh S. Jaini
mentions the story of the Jain asked about the whereabouts of
a deer by a hunter, and, after supporting a deer-saving lie,
he notes that "the Jaina teachers have taken the exigencies
of worldly existence into account, functionally defining
asatya for the layman as a lie for one's own sake." With
monks, however, "no such expedient solution is
available."[38] So, it appears, the monks have vowed to avoid
lies even to help others, and this would surely mean that
they would be unlikely to engage in deliberate global
deception.
But what about the "incredible" teachings? Jaini says that
someone who has perfected nihsankita, freedom from doubt, is
"free of skepticism and perplexity regarding the teachings of
the Jina. He accepts these teachings without reservation,
partly because of his own glimpse into reality and partly
because he realizes that a Jina, totally omniscient and free
of all passions, can preach nothing but the absolute
truth."[39] So, whatever we ourselves believe about the Jain
picture of the universe, we should probably believe that the
advanced Jain who teaches it also believes it. Now, if we
could only be confident that the concept of an "omniscient
passionless Jina" is not itself a convenient fiction.
I do not understand precisely why a passionless omniscient
Jina is incapable of deception, but the reason ordinary Jains
avoid lies is similar to the reason they avoid harm. Jains
take the concept of karma so seriously that we can doubt if
they even entertain the possibility that it might be a
convenient fiction. As a result of this karmaphobia, they are
relentlessly careful to avoid doing even the least harm
(himsa) to any of the billions of living beings. For this
reason, perhaps, satya (truthfulness) is second only to
ahirnsa in the Jain table of virtues. Someone who inflicts a
deliberate deception upon a large number of beings becomes
responsible for all the harm that results when the afflicted
people act in ignorance. This may be why many Jains consider
statecraft, like farming, to be a less than desirable
occupation.
B. The Daoists. Of the places in the Dao De Jing where
truthfulness comes up, two seem to promote it. In number 8
the best man is said to love faithfulness in words, and in
number 17 the "great rulers" are said to value their words
highly? Others passages, however, have been seen as
recommending deception. In number 3 the sage is said to
keep the hearts (minds) of his people empty and their
bellies full, and in number 65 it is said that in ancient
times the sage "did not seek to enlighten the people, but
to make them ignorant," and that "people are difficult to
govern because they have too much knowledge." Further,
number 36 is always cited as promoting a doctrine of
deceit:
In order to contract, it is necessary first to expand.
In order to weaken, it is necessary first to strengthen.
In order to destroy, it is necessary first to promote.
In order to grasp, it is necessary first to give.
Wing-tsit Chan, the translator, notes that "Ch'eng I condemns
these methods as outright deceit," and relates how "
citing the same saying, attacks Lao Tzu as irresponsible and
taking advantage of others." But Chan rejects the teachings
of these "Confucianists/' and concludes that "to think that
Taoism teaches treachery is nearly impossible."[41 ] I agree,
and would add that it is far from obvious that numbers 3, 65,
or 36 must be read as advocating wholesale deception. Someone
who expands is not saying or implying that he is never going
to contract, and empty minds are not filled with false
information.
The best support for the claim that the Daoist would not
exploit convenient fictions comes from number 49:
The sage has no fixed (personal)ideas. He regards the
people's ideas as his own.... I am honest to those who
are honest, And I am also honest to those who are not
honest. Thus honesty is attained. The sage, in the
governance of his empire, has no subjective viewpoint.
His mind forms a harmonious whole with that of his
people. They all lend their eyes and ears, and he treats
them all as infants.
This is a strong endorsement of truthfulness and the lack of
duplicity in government. If the Daoist governing an empire
has no "subjective viewpoint, " then, unlike traditional
leaders, he has no personal program to impose on the people.
He will simply be the embodiment of the "general will," in
which case there will be no logical space for duplicity.
C. The Legalists. The Legalists were so concerned with the
impersonal operation of the machine of the state that they
would not have wanted to gum up the works with false
beliefs. They would not even bother, as Mo Zi did, to
frighten the people with tales of gods, ghosts, and the
anger of Heaven[42] The Legalist ruler simply sets out the
laws and the schedule of reward and punishment, and then
lets things happen according to the book. According to Han
Fei Zi, the ruler controls the people by the laws, and he
controls his ministers by means of the two handles of
punishment and reward.[43] If the ruler has a monopoly on
the means of coercion, then deception isn't worth the
effort.
This is not to say that the Legalists were free of all
duplicity. Deception and falsehood were used to manipulate
and conquer other states. Moreover, Han Fei Zi urged the
ruler not to reveal his will and preferences to his ministers
or his people, lest they "put on the mask that pleases
him."[44]
The Daoist runs the state with nonaction by having no mind of
his own, and the Legalist runs it with nonaction by starting
the machinery of the laws and then allowing things to
function automatically. The (ideal) Daoist has no motive for
promoting convenient fictions, and the Legalist (ideally) has
no need to do so. The Jain, by way of contrast, has a strong
motive not to deceive, and, perhaps for that very reason, a
strong motive not to try to run the state.
7. Convenient Fictions Today
The distinction between a lie and a "nonmendacious" deception
is not as sharp as people often suppose. The focus of this
essay has never been on lying alone, but rather on the
deliberate and large-scale promotion and exploitation of
false beliefs. The Daoist ruler might have had some hope of
keeping the people ignorant, and the Legalist of remaining
mysterious and hidden, even from his ministers, but such
policies are more difficult to carry out now than they were
in the days of the First Emperor of
networks, shortwave radios, investigative reporters, CNN,
tabloid TV, fax machines, and camcorders, it is hard to
remain ignorant, and hard to keep secret anything someone
wants to know.
The technology of duplicity has almost kept pace with the
technology of discovery, but what makes duplicity more
difficult than discovery is the interconnectedness of beliefs
and of people. A noble whopper is connected by consistency
requirements to a vast number of other beliefs that will have
to be readjusted if the lie is to be accepted. Every
commonsense belief that doesn't fit is a thorn in the side of
the fiction, as is every nonbeliever who insists on sticking
with common sense, or Richard Garner with a different
fiction. The technology of revelation (and the freedom to use
it) allows everyone who hears the lie also to hear, and
sometimes even to see, the truth.
Convenient fictions that introduce devils and hells, karma
and reincarnation, and the stern voice of duty (beings and
processes that cannot be observed at work) are more difficult
to maintain now because we have a better understanding of
natural phenomena, including ourselves, than we did when the
fictions were first introduced. We are no longer forced to
settle for what may have been the best available explanation
several thousand years ago.
There are, of course, billions of people whose choices are
influenced by beliefs that are literally false. Some of those
who teach and exploit these false doctrines sincerely believe
them. But in other cases, the false beliefs are promoted by
cynical leaders who do not subscribe to them. It is not a
sure thing, but I am willing to predict that in the
twenty-first century it will be more difficult for
authoritarian and paternalistic leaders to administer "the
medicine of deception" to people, who (with some regrettable
exceptions) seem to be in the process of deciding that the
medicine they really need is the truth.
Truth is vital in a democracy, and if indeed the world is
heading in that direction we should try to flush out as many
convenient fictions from our systems as we can. It is
important for the citizens of a democracy to know the costs
of the alternatives and to hear the other hard truths
politicians like to conceal. It is not the task of the
philosopher to stand in the way of someone looking for
information, or to hamper that vital activity by withholding
criticism of outdated myths or creating new ones.
Even a truth-loving philosopher may decide to save a life or
a feeling by telling a lie, and there is certainly no need to
be militant about debunking every "superstition," but it has
always been the task of the philosopher to discover and share
the truth. In this case, the truth is that we are deceiving
ourselves if we think that some cherished end can be gained
and sustained by systematic deception, or that there are no
bad side effects when some presumptuous elite manipulates
everyone else by promoting a version of events they know to
be inaccurate.
NOTES
I would like to thank the instructors and participants of the
1989 NEH Summer Institute on Nagarjuna and Buddhist Thought
for making me think hard about the Buddhist notion of
convenient means. I am grateful also to Richard Bjornson at
Ohio State and to the anonymous reviewers for this Journal,
whose comments forced me to write a better essay. I think of
this work as an initial attempt to stake out my "pro-truth"
position, but by no means do I suppose that it is the whole
truth about well-meant falsehoods.
1. I did not say 'by those who believe they are false'
because I am confident that in the three cases I am going
to discuss, the beliefs in question are not true.
Obviously that is not the issue here. I should also
mention that l will avoid loose-ends complications such
as people who teach truths they believe to be false or
falsehoods they believe to be true.
2. The
3. Ibid. See also, of course, the exchange with Cephalus
about the madman with the knife (p. 7). Here the question
is whether or not to tell a lie to save a life--not a
difficult question unless you have for some reason
unwisely adopted an absolute prohibition on lies. A
similar story turns up in the Mahabharata and in Jain
literature, though in the Jain version of the story the
lie is elicited by a hunter chasing a deer rather than a
robber searching for his victims or a madman searching
for a murder instrument (Padmanabh S. Jaini, The Jaina
Path of Purification [
Press, 1979], p. 174). The Jain may have taken a vow of
truthfulness, but in the case in question, he will
protect the deer with a lie or with silence. Kant raises
the issue and argues that it is wrong to lie even to save
someone from being murdered. "To be truthful (honest) in
all declarations, " he says, "is a sacred and absolutely
commanding decree of reason, limited by no expediency"
("On a Supposed Right to Lie from Altruistic Motives," in
Critique of Practical Reason and other Writings in Moral
Philosophy, trans. Lewis W. Beck [
Publishing Company, 1976], p. 348). These occasional lies
for the sake of others, or even for our own sake, pale to
insignificance when compared with the lies on which we
are focusing--the well-intentioned but massive
fabrications devised to affect the thoughts and actions
of everyone.
4. Ibid., p. 78.
5. Ibid., p. 158.
6. Ibid., p. 159.
7. Ibid., p. 68.
8. Ibid., p. 106. Why did Plato refrain from accepting what
seems to be the actual import of this myth--namely, that
it is not all citizens who are brothers and sisters, but
all people?
9. Ibid., pp. 106-107. Richard Garner
10. Ibid., p. 106, n. 1. See also his remarks about the
Greek term 'psuedos' on p. 68. In Jowett's translation it
is called a "needful falsehood," and in Rouse's a
"necessary lie."
11. A Sourcebook in Indian Philosophy, ed. Sarvepalli
Radhakrishnan and Charles A.
University Press, 1957), p. 19.
12. Scripture of the Lotus Blossom of the Fine Dharma (The
Lotus Sutra), trans. Leon Hurvitz (
University Press, 1976). The Lotus Sutra goes on at
length about various hells and disagreeable
reincarnations that are reserved for people who malign
and disbelieve it (see chap. 3, "Parable," pp. 77 ff).
13. Ibid., chap. 2, "Expedient Devices," p. 25.
14. Ibid., p. xx.
15. Ibid., chap. 3, p. 60.
16. The father did in fact lie, but that may be the least
interesting aspect of his behavior. It is never stated,
but it is made abundantly clear, that this lord set
himself up for the situation that forced the lie. Why did
he store his "beloved" children in a dilapidated fire
trap? Why did he allow them to become addicted to toys?
Most importantly, what sort of training did he give them
that they responded to a promise of toys but wouldn't
even listen when he warned them of a real danger? The
moral I get from the story, and it is a very important
one, is that if we allow things to develop in certain
directions, we are sure to find ourselves in situations
where we can avert an undesirable outcome only by doing
something we would not normally allow ourselves to
do--like lying or deceiving someone who is close to us.
17. David Hume, Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals,
ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge (
1902), p. 294 (Appendix 1).
18. David Hume, 4 Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A.
Selby-Bigge (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1888), III.
1.i, pp. 468-469.
19. Ibid., p. 469.
20. J. L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong
(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1977), p. 35.
21. Ibid., p. 170.
22. Ibid., p. 173.
23. Simon Blackburn, Spreading the Word(
Clarendon Press, 1984), and "Errors and the Phenomenology
of Value, " in Morality and Objectivity, ed. T. Honderich
(Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1985).
24.
25. J. L. Mackie, Hume's Moral Theory (
Kegan Paul, 1980), p. 75.
26.
6.
times he seems to be rejecting the error theory as such,
and at other times he seems to allow that people do have
false beliefs about moral objectivity (a "false theory,"
he says) but that "it does not follow that the error
infects the practice of moralizing, nor the concepts used
in ways defined by that practice" (p. 3). He does not
explain how a false theory about what you are doing can
be insulated from your practice and your concepts.
27. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, 111.2.ii, p. 477.
28. Ibid., p. 495.
29. Mackie, Ethics, p. 190.
30. Ibid., p. 106.
31. Ibid., p. 123.
32. See Richard T. Garner, "On the Genuine Queerness of
Moral Properties and Facts," The Australasian Journal of
Philosophy 68, no. 2 (June 1990): 137-146.
33.
34. Ibid., p. 8.
35. Sissela Bok, Lying (New York, Vintage Books, 1979), pp.
21 ff.
36. Jeffrey Hopkins, Compassion in Tibetan Buddhism
(Ithaca, New York: Snow Lion Publications, 1980), pp.
77-78. In his comment on Chandrakirti, Tsong-ka-pa says
this:
Chandrakirti says in his commentary to Aryadeva's Four
Hundred, that if sentient beings are considered to have
been friends much as parents--from beginningless time,
then one can bear to plunge into cyclic existence for
their sake (p. 119).
37. Jagmanderlal Jaini, Outlines of Jainism (
University Press, 1916), pp. 119-125.
38. Padmanabh S. Jaini, The Jaina Path of Purification, p.
174.
39. Ibid., p. 151.
40. Wing-tsit Chan, The Way of Lao Tzu (
Bobbs-Merrill, 1963).
41. Ibid., p. 164.
42. See Mo Zi's chapter on "The Will of Heaven" and the
chapter on "Explaining Ghosts," where he says that "if we
could only make all the people in the world believe that
the ghosts and spirits have the Richard Garner power to
reward the worthy and punish the wicked, then how could
there be any disorder in the world" (Basic Writings of Mo
Tzu, Hsun Tzu, and Han Fei Tzu, trans.
p. 94).
43. Ibid., pt. III, p. 30.
44. Ibid., p. 16.
欢迎投稿:lianxiwo@fjdh.cn
2.佛教导航欢迎广大读者踊跃投稿,佛教导航将优先发布高质量的稿件,如果有必要,在不破坏关键事实和中心思想的前提下,佛教导航将会对原始稿件做适当润色和修饰,并主动联系作者确认修改稿后,才会正式发布。如果作者希望披露自己的联系方式和个人简单背景资料,佛教导航会尽量满足您的需求;
3.文章来源注明“佛教导航”的文章,为本站编辑组原创文章,其版权归佛教导航所有。欢迎非营利性电子刊物、网站转载,但须清楚注明来源“佛教导航”或作者“佛教导航”。
下一篇:Are psychedelics useful in the practice of Buddhism?